Namespaces
Variants
Actions

Difference between revisions of "Stability in game theory"

From Encyclopedia of Mathematics
Jump to: navigation, search
m (tex encoded by computer)
m (fixing spaces)
 
(One intermediate revision by the same user not shown)
Line 13: Line 13:
 
A principle reflecting directly or indirectly the idea of stability of a situation (or of a set of situations). One singles out the following basic concepts of stability.
 
A principle reflecting directly or indirectly the idea of stability of a situation (or of a set of situations). One singles out the following basic concepts of stability.
  
1)  $  \phi $-
+
1)  $  \phi $-stability, cf. [[Coalitional game|Coalitional game]].
stability, cf. [[Coalitional game|Coalitional game]].
 
  
2)  $  \psi $-
+
2)  $  \psi $-stability. An optimality principle in a [[Cooperative game|cooperative game]], connected with the concept of stability of pairs, consisting of a partition of the set  $  I $
stability. An optimality principle in a [[Cooperative game|cooperative game]], connected with the concept of stability of pairs, consisting of a partition of the set  $  I $
 
 
of players into coalitions and allocations relative to the formation of new coalitions. A partition  $  {\mathcal T} = ( T _ {1} \dots T _ {m} ) $
 
of players into coalitions and allocations relative to the formation of new coalitions. A partition  $  {\mathcal T} = ( T _ {1} \dots T _ {m} ) $
 
of the set  $  I $
 
of the set  $  I $
Line 26: Line 24:
 
A pair  $  ( x, {\mathcal T} ) $,  
 
A pair  $  ( x, {\mathcal T} ) $,  
 
where  $  x $
 
where  $  x $
is an allocation, is called  $  \psi $-
+
is an allocation, is called  $  \psi $-stable if  $  \sum _ {i \in S }  x _ {i} \geq  v ( S) $
stable if  $  \sum _ {i \in S }  x _ {i} \geq  v ( S) $
 
 
for all  $  S \in \psi ( {\mathcal T} ) $
 
for all  $  S \in \psi ( {\mathcal T} ) $
 
and if  $  x _ {i} > v ( \{ i \} ) $
 
and if  $  x _ {i} > v ( \{ i \} ) $
 
when  $  \{ i \} \notin {\mathcal T} $.
 
when  $  \{ i \} \notin {\mathcal T} $.
  
3)  $  k $-
+
3)  $  k $-stability. A special case of  $  \psi $-stability, when for  $  \psi ( {\mathcal T} ) $
stability. A special case of  $  \psi $-
 
stability, when for  $  \psi ( {\mathcal T} ) $
 
 
a set of coalitions is chosen, each of which differs from any element of  $  {\mathcal T} $
 
a set of coalitions is chosen, each of which differs from any element of  $  {\mathcal T} $
 
by not more than  $  k $
 
by not more than  $  k $
 
players.
 
players.
  
4)  $  M $-
+
4)  $  M $-stability. An optimality principle in the theory of cooperative games which formalizes the intuitive notion of stability of formation of coalitions and allocation of values  $  v ( T) $
stability. An optimality principle in the theory of cooperative games which formalizes the intuitive notion of stability of formation of coalitions and allocation of values  $  v ( T) $
 
 
of a characteristic function  $  v $
 
of a characteristic function  $  v $
 
defined on the set of coalitions  $  T $
 
defined on the set of coalitions  $  T $
Line 101: Line 95:
  
 
A coalitionally rational configuration  $  ( x, {\mathcal T} ) $
 
A coalitionally rational configuration  $  ( x, {\mathcal T} ) $
is called  $  M $-
+
is called  $  M $-stable if for any pair of disjoint coalitions  $  K, L $
stable if for any pair of disjoint coalitions  $  K, L $
 
 
and for every threat of  $  K $
 
and for every threat of  $  K $
 
against  $  L $
 
against  $  L $
 
there is a counter-threat of  $  L $
 
there is a counter-threat of  $  L $
 
against  $  K $.  
 
against  $  K $.  
The set of all  $  M $-
+
The set of all  $  M $-stable configurations for a coalition structure  $  {\mathcal T} $
stable configurations for a coalition structure  $  {\mathcal T} $
+
is called the  $  M $-stable set and is denoted by  $  M $
is called the  $  M $-
 
stable set and is denoted by  $  M $
 
 
or  $  M ( {\mathcal T} ) $.  
 
or  $  M ( {\mathcal T} ) $.  
 
In the case  $  \sum _ {k} v ( T _ {k} ) = v ( I) $,  
 
In the case  $  \sum _ {k} v ( T _ {k} ) = v ( I) $,  
Line 116: Line 107:
 
contains the core (cf. [[Core in the theory of games|Core in the theory of games]]) of the cooperative game  $  \langle  I, v \rangle $.  
 
contains the core (cf. [[Core in the theory of games|Core in the theory of games]]) of the cooperative game  $  \langle  I, v \rangle $.  
 
The set  $  M $
 
The set  $  M $
often turns out to be empty, and therefore one considers further the set  $  M _ {1}  ^ {(} i) $
+
often turns out to be empty, and therefore one considers further the set  $  M _ {1}  ^ {(i)} $
 
which is defined analogously to  $  M $,  
 
which is defined analogously to  $  M $,  
with the following changes: one considers not only coalitionally rational configurations, but all individually rational configurations admitting only threats and counter-threats among one-element coalitions, i.e. between individual players. It can be proved that the set  $  M _ {1}  ^ {(} i) $
+
with the following changes: one considers not only coalitionally rational configurations, but all individually rational configurations admitting only threats and counter-threats among one-element coalitions, i.e. between individual players. It can be proved that the set  $  M _ {1}  ^ {(i)} $
is non-empty for any coalition structure. The set  $  M _ {1}  ^ {(} i) $
+
is non-empty for any coalition structure. The set  $  M _ {1}  ^ {(i)} $
 
for  $  {\mathcal T} = \{ I \} $
 
for  $  {\mathcal T} = \{ I \} $
contains the  $  k $-
+
contains the  $  k $-kernel and coincides with it and the core for a [[Convex game|convex game]]  $  \langle  I, v \rangle $.
kernel and coincides with it and the core for a [[Convex game|convex game]]  $  \langle  I, v \rangle $.
 
  
The concepts of  $  M $-
+
The concepts of  $  M $-stability and  $  M _ {1}  ^ {(i)} $-stability have a natural generalization to cooperative games without side payments. It is known that in this case the set  $  M _ {1}  ^ {(i)} $
stability and  $  M _ {1}  ^ {(} i) $-
+
may be empty; there are certain conditions for  $  M _ {1}  ^ {(i)} $
stability have a natural generalization to cooperative games without side payments. It is known that in this case the set  $  M _ {1}  ^ {(} i) $
 
may be empty; there are certain conditions for  $  M _ {1}  ^ {(} i) $
 
 
to be non-empty.
 
to be non-empty.
  
 
====References====
 
====References====
 
<table><TR><TD valign="top">[1]</TD> <TD valign="top">  R.J. Aumann,  M. Maschler,  "The bargaining set for cooperative games" , ''Advances in game theory'' , Princeton Univ. Press  pp. 443–476</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[2]</TD> <TD valign="top">  N.N. Vorob'ev,  "The present state of the theory of games"  ''Russian Math. Surveys'' , '''25''' :  2  (1970)  pp. 77–150  ''Uspekhi Mat. Nauk'' , '''25''' :  2  (1970)  pp. 81–140</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[3]</TD> <TD valign="top">  R.D. Luce,  , ''Mathematical Models of Human Behaviour'' , Stanford  (1955)  pp. 32–44</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[4]</TD> <TD valign="top">  R.D. Luce,  H. Raiffa,  "Games and decisions. Introduction and critical survey" , Wiley  (1957)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[5]</TD> <TD valign="top">  B. Peleg,  "Existence theorem for the bargaining of <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/s/s086/s086970/s08697092.png" />"  ''Bull. Amer. Math. Soc.'' , '''69'''  (1963)  pp. 109–110</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[6]</TD> <TD valign="top">  B. Peleg,  "Quota games with a continuum of players"  ''Israel J. Math.'' , '''1'''  (1963)  pp. 48–53</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[7]</TD> <TD valign="top">  G. Owen,  "The theory of games" , Acad. Press  (1982)</TD></TR></table>
 
<table><TR><TD valign="top">[1]</TD> <TD valign="top">  R.J. Aumann,  M. Maschler,  "The bargaining set for cooperative games" , ''Advances in game theory'' , Princeton Univ. Press  pp. 443–476</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[2]</TD> <TD valign="top">  N.N. Vorob'ev,  "The present state of the theory of games"  ''Russian Math. Surveys'' , '''25''' :  2  (1970)  pp. 77–150  ''Uspekhi Mat. Nauk'' , '''25''' :  2  (1970)  pp. 81–140</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[3]</TD> <TD valign="top">  R.D. Luce,  , ''Mathematical Models of Human Behaviour'' , Stanford  (1955)  pp. 32–44</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[4]</TD> <TD valign="top">  R.D. Luce,  H. Raiffa,  "Games and decisions. Introduction and critical survey" , Wiley  (1957)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[5]</TD> <TD valign="top">  B. Peleg,  "Existence theorem for the bargaining of <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/s/s086/s086970/s08697092.png" />"  ''Bull. Amer. Math. Soc.'' , '''69'''  (1963)  pp. 109–110</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[6]</TD> <TD valign="top">  B. Peleg,  "Quota games with a continuum of players"  ''Israel J. Math.'' , '''1'''  (1963)  pp. 48–53</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[7]</TD> <TD valign="top">  G. Owen,  "The theory of games" , Acad. Press  (1982)</TD></TR></table>

Latest revision as of 09:38, 21 March 2022


A principle reflecting directly or indirectly the idea of stability of a situation (or of a set of situations). One singles out the following basic concepts of stability.

1) $ \phi $-stability, cf. Coalitional game.

2) $ \psi $-stability. An optimality principle in a cooperative game, connected with the concept of stability of pairs, consisting of a partition of the set $ I $ of players into coalitions and allocations relative to the formation of new coalitions. A partition $ {\mathcal T} = ( T _ {1} \dots T _ {m} ) $ of the set $ I $ of players is called a coalition structure. Let $ \langle I, v \rangle $ be a cooperative game and $ \psi $ a function associating with every coalition structure $ {\mathcal T} $ a set of coalitions $ \psi ( {\mathcal T} ) $. A pair $ ( x, {\mathcal T} ) $, where $ x $ is an allocation, is called $ \psi $-stable if $ \sum _ {i \in S } x _ {i} \geq v ( S) $ for all $ S \in \psi ( {\mathcal T} ) $ and if $ x _ {i} > v ( \{ i \} ) $ when $ \{ i \} \notin {\mathcal T} $.

3) $ k $-stability. A special case of $ \psi $-stability, when for $ \psi ( {\mathcal T} ) $ a set of coalitions is chosen, each of which differs from any element of $ {\mathcal T} $ by not more than $ k $ players.

4) $ M $-stability. An optimality principle in the theory of cooperative games which formalizes the intuitive notion of stability of formation of coalitions and allocation of values $ v ( T) $ of a characteristic function $ v $ defined on the set of coalitions $ T $ relative to the possible threat of one coalition against the others. A pair $ ( x, {\mathcal T} ) $, where $ x = ( x _ {i} ) _ {i \in I } $ is a vector satisfying the condition $ \sum _ {i \in T _ {k} } x _ {i} = v ( T _ {k} ) $, $ k = 1 \dots m $, while $ {\mathcal T} = ( T _ {1} \dots T _ {m} ) $ is a coalition structure, is called a configuration. A configuration is said to be individually rational if $ x _ {i} \geq v ( \{ i \} ) $, $ i \in I $. A configuration $ ( x, {\mathcal T} ) $ is called coalitionally rational if the vector $ x $ satisfies $ \sum _ {i \in S } x _ {i} \geq v ( S) $ for any coalition $ S \subset T _ {k} $, $ k = 1 \dots m $. In case $ \sum _ {k = 1 } ^ {m} v ( T _ {k} ) = v ( I) $, in particular when $ {\mathcal T} = \{ I \} $, for every individually rational configuration $ ( x, {\mathcal T} ) $ the vector $ x $ is an allocation.

The set $ P ( K; {\mathcal T} ) = \{ {i \in I } : {i \in T _ {k} \textrm{ and } T _ {k} \cap K \neq \emptyset } \} $ is called the set of partners of a coalition $ K \subset I $ in a coalition structure $ {\mathcal T} $. Let $ ( x, {\mathcal T} ) $ be a coalitionally rational configuration and let $ K, L \subset I $ be disjoint coalitions. A coalitionally rational configuration $ ( y, U) $ satisfying the conditions

$$ P ( K; U) \cap L = \emptyset , $$

$$ y _ {i} > x _ {i} \ \textrm{ for } \textrm{ all } i \in K, $$

$$ y _ {i} \geq x _ {i} \ \textrm{ for } \textrm{ all } i \in P ( K; U), $$

is called a threat of a coalition $ K $ against $ L $. By a counter-threat of $ L $ against $ K $ one understands a coalitionally rational configuration $ ( z, V) $ satisfying the conditions

$$ K \subset \setminus P ( L; V), $$

$$ z _ {i} \geq x _ {i} \ \textrm{ for } \textrm{ all } i \in P ( L; V), $$

$$ z _ {i} \geq y _ {i} \ \textrm{ for } \textrm{ all } i \in P ( L; V) \cap P ( K; U). $$

A coalitionally rational configuration $ ( x, {\mathcal T} ) $ is called $ M $-stable if for any pair of disjoint coalitions $ K, L $ and for every threat of $ K $ against $ L $ there is a counter-threat of $ L $ against $ K $. The set of all $ M $-stable configurations for a coalition structure $ {\mathcal T} $ is called the $ M $-stable set and is denoted by $ M $ or $ M ( {\mathcal T} ) $. In the case $ \sum _ {k} v ( T _ {k} ) = v ( I) $, the set $ M $ contains the core (cf. Core in the theory of games) of the cooperative game $ \langle I, v \rangle $. The set $ M $ often turns out to be empty, and therefore one considers further the set $ M _ {1} ^ {(i)} $ which is defined analogously to $ M $, with the following changes: one considers not only coalitionally rational configurations, but all individually rational configurations admitting only threats and counter-threats among one-element coalitions, i.e. between individual players. It can be proved that the set $ M _ {1} ^ {(i)} $ is non-empty for any coalition structure. The set $ M _ {1} ^ {(i)} $ for $ {\mathcal T} = \{ I \} $ contains the $ k $-kernel and coincides with it and the core for a convex game $ \langle I, v \rangle $.

The concepts of $ M $-stability and $ M _ {1} ^ {(i)} $-stability have a natural generalization to cooperative games without side payments. It is known that in this case the set $ M _ {1} ^ {(i)} $ may be empty; there are certain conditions for $ M _ {1} ^ {(i)} $ to be non-empty.

References

[1] R.J. Aumann, M. Maschler, "The bargaining set for cooperative games" , Advances in game theory , Princeton Univ. Press pp. 443–476
[2] N.N. Vorob'ev, "The present state of the theory of games" Russian Math. Surveys , 25 : 2 (1970) pp. 77–150 Uspekhi Mat. Nauk , 25 : 2 (1970) pp. 81–140
[3] R.D. Luce, , Mathematical Models of Human Behaviour , Stanford (1955) pp. 32–44
[4] R.D. Luce, H. Raiffa, "Games and decisions. Introduction and critical survey" , Wiley (1957)
[5] B. Peleg, "Existence theorem for the bargaining of " Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. , 69 (1963) pp. 109–110
[6] B. Peleg, "Quota games with a continuum of players" Israel J. Math. , 1 (1963) pp. 48–53
[7] G. Owen, "The theory of games" , Acad. Press (1982)
How to Cite This Entry:
Stability in game theory. Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=Stability_in_game_theory&oldid=48791
This article was adapted from an original article by A.Ya. Kiruta (originator), which appeared in Encyclopedia of Mathematics - ISBN 1402006098. See original article