Namespaces
Variants
Actions

Difference between revisions of "D0L-sequence"

From Encyclopedia of Mathematics
Jump to: navigation, search
(TeX partially done)
(TeX partially done)
Line 11: Line 11:
 
where $| \cdot |$ denotes the length of a word, and the D$0$L-language
 
where $| \cdot |$ denotes the length of a word, and the D$0$L-language
 
$$
 
$$
L(\mathcal{G}) = \{ H^i(w) : i \ge 0 \} \ .
+
L(\mathcal{G}) = \{ h^i(w) : i \ge 0 \} \ .
 
$$
 
$$
  
 
It is not only the mathematical simplicity of the definitions, but rather the challenging mathematical problems connected with these notions, in particular with D$0$L-sequences, which made D$0$L-systems mathematically very fruitful. The most famous problem is the D$0$L-sequence equivalence problem, which asks for an algorithm to decide whether or not two D$0$L-sequences coincide. The impact of this nice problem is discussed in [[#References|[a11]]].
 
It is not only the mathematical simplicity of the definitions, but rather the challenging mathematical problems connected with these notions, in particular with D$0$L-sequences, which made D$0$L-systems mathematically very fruitful. The most famous problem is the D$0$L-sequence equivalence problem, which asks for an algorithm to decide whether or not two D$0$L-sequences coincide. The impact of this nice problem is discussed in [[#References|[a11]]].
  
D$0$L-languages emphasize a static nature of the systems and are more related to classical formal language theory. D$0$L-growth sequences, in turn, are closely connected to the theory of <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001032.png" />-rational [[Formal power series|formal power series]], and in fact allow one to reformulate certain classical problems, such as the algorithmic problem on the existence of a zero in a sequence defined by a linear recurrence, see [[#References|[a15]]]. Finally, D$0$L-sequences represent a dynamical feature of the systems. Moreover, such sequences are defined in a very simple and natural way: by iterating a morphism.
+
D$0$L-languages emphasize a static nature of the systems and are more related to classical formal language theory. D$0$L-growth sequences, in turn, are closely connected to the theory of $\mathbf{N}-rational [[Formal power series|formal power series]], and in fact allow one to reformulate certain classical problems, such as the algorithmic problem on the existence of a zero in a sequence defined by a linear recurrence, see [[#References|[a15]]]. Finally, D$0$L-sequences represent a dynamical feature of the systems. Moreover, such sequences are defined in a very simple and natural way: by iterating a morphism.
  
The D$0$L-sequence equivalence problem was first shown to be algorithmically decidable in [[#References|[a4]]] (cf. also [[Proof theory|Proof theory]]). A simpler solution was found in [[#References|[a7]]], and finally a third completely different solution can be based on the validity of the [[Ehrenfeucht conjecture|Ehrenfeucht conjecture]] and Makanin's algorithm for the solvability of word equations over free monoids, as shown in [[#References|[a6]]]. It is interesting to note that only the third solution extends to a multi-dimensional variant of the D$0$L-problem, the so-called DT$0$L-sequence equivalence problem. In the latter problem, the word sequences of (a1) are replaced by <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001038.png" />-ary trees obtained by iterating <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001039.png" /> different morphisms in all possible ways.
+
The D$0$L-sequence equivalence problem was first shown to be algorithmically decidable in [[#References|[a4]]] (cf. also [[Proof theory]]). A simpler solution was found in [[#References|[a7]]], and finally a third completely different solution can be based on the validity of the [[Ehrenfeucht conjecture]] and Makanin's algorithm for the solvability of word equations over free monoids, as shown in [[#References|[a6]]]. It is interesting to note that only the third solution extends to a multi-dimensional variant of the D$0$L-problem, the so-called DT$0$L-sequence equivalence problem. In the latter problem, the word sequences of (a1) are replaced by $k$-ary trees obtained by iterating $k$ different morphisms in all possible ways.
  
 
Despite the above solutions, an intriguing feature of the D$0$L-sequence equivalence problem remains. Indeed, none of the above solutions is practical. However, it has been conjectured that only the <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001041.png" /> first elements of the sequences have to be compared in order to decide the equivalence. This <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001044.png" />-conjecture is known to hold when <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001045.png" /> is binary, see [[#References|[a10]]], but no reasonable (even exponential) bound is known (1998) in the general case.
 
Despite the above solutions, an intriguing feature of the D$0$L-sequence equivalence problem remains. Indeed, none of the above solutions is practical. However, it has been conjectured that only the <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001041.png" /> first elements of the sequences have to be compared in order to decide the equivalence. This <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001044.png" />-conjecture is known to hold when <img align="absmiddle" border="0" src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001045.png" /> is binary, see [[#References|[a10]]], but no reasonable (even exponential) bound is known (1998) in the general case.

Revision as of 19:24, 30 December 2015

$L$-systems were introduced by A. Lindenmayer in the late 1960s to model (in discrete time) the development of filamentous organisms. A fundamental feature of these systems is that in each step each cell (represented by a symbol from a finite alphabet) has to be rewritten according to the developmental rules of the organism. This parallelism is the main difference between $L$-systems and the classical Chomsky grammars (cf. also Grammar, generative). In fact, soon after their introduction, $L$-systems constituted a significant part of formal language theory, allowing one to compare parallel rewriting to a more classical sequential one, see [a13].

The simplest $L$-system is a so-called D$0$L-system, where the development starts from a single word and continues deterministically step by step in a context independent way, that is, the development of a symbol depends only on that symbol. (Here, "D" stands for determinism, $0$ for zero-sided interaction and "L" for Lindenmayer.) Formally, a D$0$L-system is a triple $\mathcal{G} = (\Sigma,h,w)$, where $\Sigma$ is a finite alphabet, $h$ is an endomorphism of the free monoid generated by $\Sigma$, in symbols $\Sigma^*$, and $w$ is a starting word. The system $\mathcal{G}$ defines the D$0$L-sequence $$ S(\mathcal{G})\ : \ w,\,h(w),\,h^2(w),\,\ldots $$ the D$0$L-growth sequence $$ GS(\mathcal{G})\ : \ |w|,\,|h(w)|,\,|h^2(w)|,\,\ldots $$ where $| \cdot |$ denotes the length of a word, and the D$0$L-language $$ L(\mathcal{G}) = \{ h^i(w) : i \ge 0 \} \ . $$

It is not only the mathematical simplicity of the definitions, but rather the challenging mathematical problems connected with these notions, in particular with D$0$L-sequences, which made D$0$L-systems mathematically very fruitful. The most famous problem is the D$0$L-sequence equivalence problem, which asks for an algorithm to decide whether or not two D$0$L-sequences coincide. The impact of this nice problem is discussed in [a11].

D$0$L-languages emphasize a static nature of the systems and are more related to classical formal language theory. D$0$L-growth sequences, in turn, are closely connected to the theory of $\mathbf{N}-rational [[Formal power series|formal power series]], and in fact allow one to reformulate certain classical problems, such as the algorithmic problem on the existence of a zero in a sequence defined by a linear recurrence, see [[#References|[a15]]]. Finally, D$0$L-sequences represent a dynamical feature of the systems. Moreover, such sequences are defined in a very simple and natural way: by iterating a morphism. The D$0$L-sequence equivalence problem was first shown to be algorithmically decidable in [[#References|[a4]]] (cf. also [[Proof theory]]). A simpler solution was found in [[#References|[a7]]], and finally a third completely different solution can be based on the validity of the [[Ehrenfeucht conjecture]] and Makanin's algorithm for the solvability of word equations over free monoids, as shown in [[#References|[a6]]]. It is interesting to note that only the third solution extends to a multi-dimensional variant of the D$0$L-problem, the so-called DT$0$L-sequence equivalence problem. In the latter problem, the word sequences of (a1) are replaced by $k$-ary trees obtained by iterating $k$ different morphisms in all possible ways. Despite the above solutions, an intriguing feature of the D$0$L-sequence equivalence problem remains. Indeed, none of the above solutions is practical. However, it has been conjectured that only the <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001041.png"/> first elements of the sequences have to be compared in order to decide the equivalence. This <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001044.png"/>-conjecture is known to hold when <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001045.png"/> is binary, see [[#References|[a10]]], but no reasonable (even exponential) bound is known (1998) in the general case. As already hinted at, the major mathematical importance of D$0$L-systems lies in the fact that they (in particular, the research on the D$0$L-sequence equivalence problem) motivated a large amount of fundamental research on morphisms of free monoids. Below a few such examples are given. Consider a [[morphism]] <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001048.png"/> satisfying <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001049.png"/> for some <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001050.png"/> and <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001051.png"/>. If <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001052.png"/> is non-erasing, i.e. <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001053.png"/> for all <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001054.png"/>, then there exists a unique infinite word <table class="eq" style="width:100%;"> <tr><td valign="top" style="width:94%;text-align:center;"><img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001055.png"/></td> </tr></table> Consequently, D$0$L-sequences can be used in a very natural way to define infinite words. Implicitly, A. Thue used this approach at the beginning of the 20th century in his seminal work on square- and cube-free infinite words over a finite alphabet, see [[#References|[a16]]]. Since the early 1980s, such a research on non-repetitive words, revitalized by [[#References|[a2]]], has been a central topic in the combinatorics of words. Almost exclusively non-repetitive words are constructed by the above method of iterating a morphism. The D$0$L-sequence equivalence problem asks whether or not two morphism <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001059.png"/> and <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001060.png"/> agree on a D$0$L-language defined by one of the morphisms, that is, whether or not <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001062.png"/> for all <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001063.png"/> in <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001064.png"/>. This has motivated the consideration of so-called equality languages of two morphisms <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001065.png"/>: <table class="eq" style="width:100%;"> <tr><td valign="top" style="width:94%;text-align:center;"><img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001066.png"/></td> </tr></table> Research on equality languages revealed amazing morphic characterizations of recursively enumerable languages, see [[#References|[a3]]], [[#References|[a8]]] and [[#References|[a14]]]. For example, each recursively enumerable language (cf. also [[Formal languages and automata|Formal languages and automata]]) can be expressed in the form <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001067.png"/>, where <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001068.png"/> and <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001069.png"/> are morphisms and <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001070.png"/> is a regular language (cf. also [[Grammar, regular|Grammar, regular]]). Furthermore, the fundamental [[Post correspondence problem]] can be formulated as a problem of deciding whether or not <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001071.png"/>, where <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001072.png"/> denotes the unit of the free monoid <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001073.png"/>. A third, and apparently the most fundamental, consequence of research on D$0$L-systems was a discovery of a compactness property of free semi-groups: Each system of equations over a free monoid containing a finite number of variables is equivalent to some of its finite subsystems (cf. also [[Free semi-group]]). This property (often referred to as the Ehrenfeucht conjecture) was conjectured by A. Ehrenfeucht in the early 1970s (in a slightly different form) and later established in [[#References|[a1]]] and [[#References|[a9]]]. Finally, it is worth mentioning that besides their mathematical inspiration, D$0$L-sequences have turned out to be useful in areas such as computer graphics and simulation of biological developments, see [[#References|[a5]]] and [[#References|[a12]]]. ===='"`UNIQ--h-0--QINU`"'References==== <table> <tr><td valign="top">[a1]</td> <td valign="top"> M. Albert, J. Lawrence, "A proof of Ehrenfeucht's conjecture" ''Theoret. Comput. Sci.'' , '''41''' (1985) pp. 121–123</td></tr> <tr><td valign="top">[a2]</td> <td valign="top"> J. Bertel, "Mots sans carré et morphismes itérés" ''Discrete Math.'' , '''29''' (1979) pp. 235–244</td></tr> <tr><td valign="top">[a3]</td> <td valign="top"> K. Culik II, "A purely homomorphic characterization of recursively enumerable sets" ''J. Assoc. Comput. Mach.'' , '''26''' (1979) pp. 345–350</td></tr> <tr><td valign="top">[a4]</td> <td valign="top"> K. Culik II, I. Fris, "The decidability of the equivalence problem for D0L-systems" ''Inform. Control'' , '''35''' (1977) pp. 20–39</td></tr> <tr><td valign="top">[a5]</td> <td valign="top"> K. Culik II, J. Kari, "On the power of <img src="https://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/legacyimages/d/d120/d120010/d12001076.png"/>-systems in image generation" G. Rozenberg (ed.) A. Salomaa (ed.) , ''Developments in Language Theory'' , World Sci. (1994) pp. 225–236</td></tr> <tr><td valign="top">[a6]</td> <td valign="top"> K. Culik II, J. Karhumäki, "Systems of equations over a free monoid and Ehrenfeucht's Conjecture" ''Discrete Math.'' , '''43''' (1983) pp. 139–153</td></tr> <tr><td valign="top">[a7]</td> <td valign="top"> A. Ehrenfeucht, G. Rozenberg, "Elementary homomorphisms and a solution to D$0$L-sequence equivalence problem" ''Theoret. Comput. Sci.'' , '''7''' (1978) pp. 169–183</td></tr> <tr><td valign="top">[a8]</td> <td valign="top"> J. Engelfriet, G. Rozenberg, "Fixed point languages, equality languages, and representation of recursively enumerable languages" ''J. Assoc. Comput. Mach.'' , '''27''' (1980) pp. 499–518</td></tr> <tr><td valign="top">[a9]</td> <td valign="top"> V.S. Guba, "The equivalence of infinite systems of equations in free groups and semigroups with finite subsystems" ''Mat. Zametki'' , '''40''' (1986) pp. 321–324 (In Russian)</td></tr> <tr><td valign="top">[a10]</td> <td valign="top"> J. Karhumäki, "On the equivalence problem for binary D0L systems" ''Inform. Control'' , '''50''' (1981) pp. 276–284</td></tr> <tr><td valign="top">[a11]</td> <td valign="top"> J. Karhumäki, "The impact of the D$0$L-problem" G. Rozenberg (ed.) A. Salomaa (ed.) , ''Current Trends in Theoretical Computer Science. Essays and Tutorials'' , World Sci. (1993) pp. 586–594</td></tr> <tr><td valign="top">[a12]</td> <td valign="top"> P. Prusinkiewicz, M. Hammel, J. Hanan, R. Měch, "Visual models of plant development" G. Rozenberg (ed.) A. Salomaa (ed.) , ''Handbook of Formal Languages'' , '''III''' , Springer (1997) pp. 535–597</td></tr> <tr><td valign="top">[a13]</td> <td valign="top"> G. Rozenberg, A. Salomaa, "The mathematical theory of $L$-systems" , Acad. Press (1980) [a14] A. Salomaa, "Equality sets for homomorphisms of free monoids" Acta Cybernetica , 4 (1978) pp. 127–139 [a15] A. Salomaa, M. Soittola, "Automata-theoretic aspects of formal power series" , Springer (1978) [a16] A. Thue, "Über unendliche Zeichereichen" Kra. Vidensk. Selsk. Skr. I. Mat.-Nat. Kl. , 7 (1906)

How to Cite This Entry:
D0L-sequence. Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=D0L-sequence&oldid=37184
This article was adapted from an original article by J. Karhumäki (originator), which appeared in Encyclopedia of Mathematics - ISBN 1402006098. See original article