Namespaces
Variants
Actions

Utility theory

From Encyclopedia of Mathematics
Revision as of 09:14, 7 April 2018 by Richard Pinch (talk | contribs) (cf. Pre-order)
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)
Jump to: navigation, search

A theory dealing with individual preferences and the representation of these by numerical functions. A preference relation on a set of alternatives $X$ is a complete transitive binary relation $R$ on $X$ (cf. Pre-order); it is represented by a function $u(x)$ on $X$, and $u(x)$ is called a utility function if for any $x,y \in X$ it follows from $x R y$ that $u(x) \ge u(y)$, and vice versa. Therefore utility theory deals with ordered sets and their monotone mappings into a numerical space (usually one-dimensional). Utility theory arose from researches by economists in the 18th century; the basis of modern utility theory was laid in the 1940s by J. von Neumann and O. Morgenstern [1].

It is obvious that a utility function exists in the case of a finite set $X$. In the infinite case, a necessary and sufficient condition for the existence of a utility function is the existence of a utility-dense countable subset $A \subset X$, i.e. for any $x,y \in X \setminus A$ such that $x R^* y$, there exists a $z \in A$ such that $x R^* z$ and $z R^* y$, where $R^*$ is a strong preference relation ($x R^* y \Leftrightarrow x R y$ and not $y R x$). If $X$ is a convex set in a vector space, $R$ is continuous on $X$ and for any $x,y,z \in X$, $x R^* y$, and any $\alpha$, $0 < \alpha < 1$, it is true that $[\alpha x + (1-\alpha)z] R^* [\alpha y + (1-\alpha)z]$, then there exists a linear utility function that is unique, up to a positive linear transformation [3]. Various combinations of weaker conditions lead to non-linear, discontinuous, or in some sense non-unique, utility functions. For example, if $X$ is a vector space, if it follows from $x R^* y$ that $[x+z] R^* [y+z]$ and if $[\alpha x] R^* [\alpha y]$ for all $z \in X$ and $\alpha > 0$, the function is single-valued and piecewise linear.

Utility theory also deals with stochastic ordering and ordering of the sums or differences of alternatives (in that case the utility function is constructed from a certain quaternary relation on $X$), as well as with generalizations to $n$-ary relations instead of binary ones, with the construction of a utility function at the same time with subjective probabilities, with the relation between the utility of multi-component alternatives and the utilities of the components, etc., [3], [4].

References

[1] J. von Neumann, O. Morgenstern, "Theory of games and economic behavior" , Princeton Univ. Press (1947)
[2] G. Birkhoff, "Lattice theory" , Colloq. Publ. , 25 , Amer. Math. Soc. (1973)
[3] P.S. Fishburn, "Utility theory for decision making" , Wiley (1970)
[4] P. Suppes, J. Zines, "Psychological measurements" , Moscow (1967) (In Russian; translated from English)


Comments

Among other aspects of utility theory, one might mention transferable utility [a4], incomplete preferences [a1], non-standard utilities [a7], as well as the large body of literature concerning the (non-) significance of utility representations for economic theory (see, e.g., [a5] and [a6], but in the special case of concavifiable preference orderings one gets some measure of cardinal utility functions [a2], [a3]).

References

[a1] R.J. Aumann, , Human Judgement and Optimality , Wiley (1964) pp. 217–242
[a2] Y. Kannai, "The ALEP definition of complementary and least concave utility functions" J. Economic Th. , 22 (1980) pp. 115–117
[a3] Y. Kannai, , Generalized Concavity in Optimization and Economics , Acad. Press (1981) pp. 543–611
[a4] R.D. Luce, H. Raiffa, "Games and decisions. Introduction and critical survey" , Wiley (1957)
[a5] P.A. Samuelson, "Foundations of economic analysis" , Harvard Univ. Press (1947)
[a6] P.A. Samuelson, J. Economic Literature , 12 (1974) pp. 1255–1289
[a7] H. Skala, "Nonstandard utilities and the foundations of game theory" Internat. J. Game Theory , 3 (1974) pp. 67–81
[a8] R.M. Thrall (ed.) C.H. Coombs (ed.) R.L. Davis (ed.) , Decision processes , Wiley (1954)
[a9] K.J. Arrow, F.H. Hahn, "General competitive analysis" , Oliver & Boyd (1971)
[a10] G. Debreu, "Continuity properties of Paretian utility" Int. Econ. Review , 5 (1964) pp. 285–293
[a11] J.T. Rader, "The existence of a utility function to represent preferences" Rev. of Econ. Studies , XXX (1963) pp. 229–232
How to Cite This Entry:
Utility theory. Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=Utility_theory&oldid=43098
This article was adapted from an original article by E.I. Vilkas (originator), which appeared in Encyclopedia of Mathematics - ISBN 1402006098. See original article