Difference between revisions of "Spread (in intuitionistic logic)"
(Importing text file) |
Ulf Rehmann (talk | contribs) m (tex encoded by computer) |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
− | + | <!-- | |
+ | s0868901.png | ||
+ | $#A+1 = 49 n = 0 | ||
+ | $#C+1 = 49 : ~/encyclopedia/old_files/data/S086/S.0806890 Spread (in intuitionistic logic) | ||
+ | Automatically converted into TeX, above some diagnostics. | ||
+ | Please remove this comment and the {{TEX|auto}} line below, | ||
+ | if TeX found to be correct. | ||
+ | --> | ||
− | + | {{TEX|auto}} | |
+ | {{TEX|done}} | ||
− | + | A notion in intuitionistic mathematics (see [[Intuitionism|Intuitionism]]). It is a population, a [[Species|species]], consisting of finite sequences (cf. [[Tuple|Tuple]]) of positive integers, called the nodes of the spread (or the admissible sequences of the spread). More precisely, a species $ \Pi $ | |
+ | of sequences of natural numbers is called a spread if the following conditions are satisfied: 1) there exists an effective rule $ a $( | ||
+ | a so-called spread law) by which for any sequences $ \langle n _ {1} \dots n _ {m} \rangle $ | ||
+ | one can determine whether or not it is a node of $ \Pi $; | ||
+ | 2) the empty sequence $ \langle \rangle $ | ||
+ | is a node of any spread; 3) if the sequence $ \langle n _ {1} \dots n _ {m} \rangle $ | ||
+ | is a node of the spread, then any initial sequence of it, of the form $ \langle n _ {1} \dots n _ {i} \rangle $ | ||
+ | for $ i \leq m $, | ||
+ | is also a node of $ \Pi $; | ||
+ | and 4) if the sequence $ \langle n _ {1} \dots n _ {m} \rangle $ | ||
+ | is a node of $ \Pi $, | ||
+ | then there exists a positive integer $ k $ | ||
+ | such that $ \langle n _ {1} \dots n _ {m} , k \rangle $ | ||
+ | is a node of $ \Pi $. | ||
− | < | + | If one orders the sequences of positive integers by considering that $ \tau < \pi $ |
+ | if and only if $ \tau $ | ||
+ | is a proper initial part of $ \pi $, | ||
+ | then from the point of view of this order the spread $ \Pi $ | ||
+ | is an infinite tree with origin $ \langle \rangle $, | ||
+ | given effectively (given by a law). A choice sequence $ \alpha $( | ||
+ | or, more generally, an arbitrary effective function converting natural numbers into natural numbers) is called an element of a spread $ \Pi $, | ||
+ | symbolically $ \alpha \in \Pi $, | ||
+ | if for any $ n $ | ||
+ | the sequence $ \langle \alpha ( 0) \dots \alpha ( n - 1 ) \rangle $ | ||
+ | is a node of $ \Pi $. | ||
+ | In applications one often has to deal with the notion of a labelled spread. A labelled spread $ \Gamma $ | ||
+ | consists of a spread $ \Pi $ | ||
+ | and an effective rule $ \Gamma _ \Pi $( | ||
+ | the so-called complementary spread law) attributing to each node $ \pi $ | ||
+ | of $ \Pi $ | ||
+ | some object $ \Gamma _ \Pi ( \pi ) $. | ||
+ | Thus there is a natural correspondence between each element of the spread $ \Pi $ | ||
+ | and a sequence of objects given by the law $ \Gamma _ \Pi $. | ||
− | + | In the language of formal intuitionistic mathematical analysis a spread is given by a function — its spread law. With that end in view one considers the standard primitive recursive one-to-one correspondence between sequences of natural numbers and natural numbers. Let the tuple $ \langle \rangle $ | |
+ | correspond to $ 0 $, | ||
+ | let the operation of concatenating two sequences be coded by a primitive recursive function $ x * y $, | ||
+ | and let $ \widehat{x} $ | ||
+ | denote the number of the sequence with unique element $ x $. | ||
+ | The statement that the tuple with number $ x $ | ||
+ | is a node of the spread given by $ a $ | ||
+ | is written as $ a ( x) = 0 $. | ||
+ | Then the formula $ \mathop{\rm Spr} ( a) $ | ||
+ | describing the notion "the function a defines a spread" is written in the form | ||
− | + | $$ | |
+ | a ( 0) = 0 \& \forall x y ( a ( x * y ) = 0 \supset a ( x) = 0 ) \& | ||
+ | $$ | ||
+ | |||
+ | $$ | ||
+ | \& \ | ||
+ | \forall x ( a ( x) = 0 \supset \exists y ( a ( x * \widehat{y} ) = 0 ) ) . | ||
+ | $$ | ||
+ | |||
+ | Finally, if by $ \overline \alpha \; ( n) $ | ||
+ | one denotes the number of the sequence $ \langle \alpha ( 0) \dots \alpha ( n - 1 ) \rangle $, | ||
+ | where $ n $ | ||
+ | is the length of the sequence, then the formula $ \alpha \in a $( | ||
+ | "a is an element of the spread given by a" ) is written as $ \forall x a ( \overline \alpha \; ( x) ) = 0 $. | ||
In the foundations of mathematics, generalizations of the concept of a spread, in which sequences of natural numbers are replaced by sequences of more complicated objects (for example, by sequences consisting of choice sequences) are also considered. | In the foundations of mathematics, generalizations of the concept of a spread, in which sequences of natural numbers are replaced by sequences of more complicated objects (for example, by sequences consisting of choice sequences) are also considered. | ||
Line 15: | Line 76: | ||
====References==== | ====References==== | ||
<table><TR><TD valign="top">[1]</TD> <TD valign="top"> A. Heyting, "Intuitionism: an introduction" , North-Holland (1970)</TD></TR></table> | <table><TR><TD valign="top">[1]</TD> <TD valign="top"> A. Heyting, "Intuitionism: an introduction" , North-Holland (1970)</TD></TR></table> | ||
− | |||
− | |||
====Comments==== | ====Comments==== | ||
− | |||
====References==== | ====References==== | ||
<table><TR><TD valign="top">[a1]</TD> <TD valign="top"> M.A.E. Dummett, "Elements of intuitionism" , Oxford Univ. Press (1977)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a2]</TD> <TD valign="top"> A.S. Troelstra, D. van Dalen, "Constructivism in mathematics, an introduction" , '''1–2''' , North-Holland (1988–1989)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a3]</TD> <TD valign="top"> A.S. Troelstra, "Principles of intuitionism" , Springer (1969)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a4]</TD> <TD valign="top"> A.S. Troelstra, "Choice sequences" , Clarendon Press (1977)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a5]</TD> <TD valign="top"> G. van der Hoeven, I. Moerdijk, "On choice sequences determined by spreads" ''J. Symbolic Logic'' , '''49''' (1984) pp. 908–916</TD></TR></table> | <table><TR><TD valign="top">[a1]</TD> <TD valign="top"> M.A.E. Dummett, "Elements of intuitionism" , Oxford Univ. Press (1977)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a2]</TD> <TD valign="top"> A.S. Troelstra, D. van Dalen, "Constructivism in mathematics, an introduction" , '''1–2''' , North-Holland (1988–1989)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a3]</TD> <TD valign="top"> A.S. Troelstra, "Principles of intuitionism" , Springer (1969)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a4]</TD> <TD valign="top"> A.S. Troelstra, "Choice sequences" , Clarendon Press (1977)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a5]</TD> <TD valign="top"> G. van der Hoeven, I. Moerdijk, "On choice sequences determined by spreads" ''J. Symbolic Logic'' , '''49''' (1984) pp. 908–916</TD></TR></table> |
Latest revision as of 08:22, 6 June 2020
A notion in intuitionistic mathematics (see Intuitionism). It is a population, a species, consisting of finite sequences (cf. Tuple) of positive integers, called the nodes of the spread (or the admissible sequences of the spread). More precisely, a species $ \Pi $
of sequences of natural numbers is called a spread if the following conditions are satisfied: 1) there exists an effective rule $ a $(
a so-called spread law) by which for any sequences $ \langle n _ {1} \dots n _ {m} \rangle $
one can determine whether or not it is a node of $ \Pi $;
2) the empty sequence $ \langle \rangle $
is a node of any spread; 3) if the sequence $ \langle n _ {1} \dots n _ {m} \rangle $
is a node of the spread, then any initial sequence of it, of the form $ \langle n _ {1} \dots n _ {i} \rangle $
for $ i \leq m $,
is also a node of $ \Pi $;
and 4) if the sequence $ \langle n _ {1} \dots n _ {m} \rangle $
is a node of $ \Pi $,
then there exists a positive integer $ k $
such that $ \langle n _ {1} \dots n _ {m} , k \rangle $
is a node of $ \Pi $.
If one orders the sequences of positive integers by considering that $ \tau < \pi $ if and only if $ \tau $ is a proper initial part of $ \pi $, then from the point of view of this order the spread $ \Pi $ is an infinite tree with origin $ \langle \rangle $, given effectively (given by a law). A choice sequence $ \alpha $( or, more generally, an arbitrary effective function converting natural numbers into natural numbers) is called an element of a spread $ \Pi $, symbolically $ \alpha \in \Pi $, if for any $ n $ the sequence $ \langle \alpha ( 0) \dots \alpha ( n - 1 ) \rangle $ is a node of $ \Pi $. In applications one often has to deal with the notion of a labelled spread. A labelled spread $ \Gamma $ consists of a spread $ \Pi $ and an effective rule $ \Gamma _ \Pi $( the so-called complementary spread law) attributing to each node $ \pi $ of $ \Pi $ some object $ \Gamma _ \Pi ( \pi ) $. Thus there is a natural correspondence between each element of the spread $ \Pi $ and a sequence of objects given by the law $ \Gamma _ \Pi $.
In the language of formal intuitionistic mathematical analysis a spread is given by a function — its spread law. With that end in view one considers the standard primitive recursive one-to-one correspondence between sequences of natural numbers and natural numbers. Let the tuple $ \langle \rangle $ correspond to $ 0 $, let the operation of concatenating two sequences be coded by a primitive recursive function $ x * y $, and let $ \widehat{x} $ denote the number of the sequence with unique element $ x $. The statement that the tuple with number $ x $ is a node of the spread given by $ a $ is written as $ a ( x) = 0 $. Then the formula $ \mathop{\rm Spr} ( a) $ describing the notion "the function a defines a spread" is written in the form
$$ a ( 0) = 0 \& \forall x y ( a ( x * y ) = 0 \supset a ( x) = 0 ) \& $$
$$ \& \ \forall x ( a ( x) = 0 \supset \exists y ( a ( x * \widehat{y} ) = 0 ) ) . $$
Finally, if by $ \overline \alpha \; ( n) $ one denotes the number of the sequence $ \langle \alpha ( 0) \dots \alpha ( n - 1 ) \rangle $, where $ n $ is the length of the sequence, then the formula $ \alpha \in a $( "a is an element of the spread given by a" ) is written as $ \forall x a ( \overline \alpha \; ( x) ) = 0 $.
In the foundations of mathematics, generalizations of the concept of a spread, in which sequences of natural numbers are replaced by sequences of more complicated objects (for example, by sequences consisting of choice sequences) are also considered.
References
[1] | A. Heyting, "Intuitionism: an introduction" , North-Holland (1970) |
Comments
References
[a1] | M.A.E. Dummett, "Elements of intuitionism" , Oxford Univ. Press (1977) |
[a2] | A.S. Troelstra, D. van Dalen, "Constructivism in mathematics, an introduction" , 1–2 , North-Holland (1988–1989) |
[a3] | A.S. Troelstra, "Principles of intuitionism" , Springer (1969) |
[a4] | A.S. Troelstra, "Choice sequences" , Clarendon Press (1977) |
[a5] | G. van der Hoeven, I. Moerdijk, "On choice sequences determined by spreads" J. Symbolic Logic , 49 (1984) pp. 908–916 |
Spread (in intuitionistic logic). Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=Spread_(in_intuitionistic_logic)&oldid=12218