Difference between revisions of "Deduction theorem"
(Importing text file) |
Ulf Rehmann (talk | contribs) m (tex encoded by computer) |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
− | + | <!-- | |
+ | d0305901.png | ||
+ | $#A+1 = 49 n = 0 | ||
+ | $#C+1 = 49 : ~/encyclopedia/old_files/data/D030/D.0300590 Deduction theorem | ||
+ | Automatically converted into TeX, above some diagnostics. | ||
+ | Please remove this comment and the {{TEX|auto}} line below, | ||
+ | if TeX found to be correct. | ||
+ | --> | ||
− | + | {{TEX|auto}} | |
+ | {{TEX|done}} | ||
− | + | A general term for a number of theorems which allow one to establish that the implication $ A \supset B $ | |
+ | can be proved if it is possible to deduce logically formula $ B $ | ||
+ | from formula $ A $. | ||
+ | In the simplest case of classical, intuitionistic, etc., propositional calculus, a deduction theorem states the following: If $ \Gamma , A \vdash B $( | ||
+ | $ B $ | ||
+ | is deducible from the assumptions $ \Gamma , A $), | ||
+ | then | ||
− | + | $$ \tag{* } | |
+ | \Gamma \vdash ( A \supset B ) | ||
+ | $$ | ||
+ | |||
+ | ( $ \Gamma $ | ||
+ | may be empty). In the presence of quantifiers an analogous statement is false: | ||
+ | |||
+ | $$ | ||
+ | A ( x) \vdash \forall x A ( x) , | ||
+ | $$ | ||
but not | but not | ||
− | + | $$ | |
+ | \vdash A ( x) \supset \forall x A ( x) . | ||
+ | $$ | ||
− | One of the formulations of a deduction theorem for traditional (classical, intuitionistic, etc.) predicate calculus is: If | + | One of the formulations of a deduction theorem for traditional (classical, intuitionistic, etc.) predicate calculus is: If $ \Gamma , A \vdash B $, |
+ | then | ||
− | + | $$ | |
+ | \Gamma \vdash ( \forall A \supset B ) , | ||
+ | $$ | ||
− | where | + | where $ \forall A $ |
+ | is the result of prefixing $ \forall $ | ||
+ | quantifiers (cf. [[Quantifier|Quantifier]]) over all the free variables of the formula $ A $. | ||
+ | In particular, if $ A $ | ||
+ | is a closed formula, a deduction theorem assumes the form (*). This formulation of a deduction theorem makes it possible to reduce proof search in axiomatic theories to proof search in predicate calculus: Formula $ B $ | ||
+ | is deducible from axioms $ A _ {1} \dots A _ {n} $ | ||
+ | if and only if the formula | ||
− | + | $$ | |
+ | \forall A _ {1} \supset ( \forall A _ {2} \supset \dots \supset ( \forall A _ {n} \supset | ||
+ | B ) \dots ) | ||
+ | $$ | ||
is deducible in predicate calculus. | is deducible in predicate calculus. | ||
Line 23: | Line 60: | ||
A deduction theorem is formulated in a similar manner for logics with operations "resembling" quantifiers. Thus, a deduction theorem has the following form for the modal logics S4 and S5 (cf. [[Modal logic|Modal logic]]): | A deduction theorem is formulated in a similar manner for logics with operations "resembling" quantifiers. Thus, a deduction theorem has the following form for the modal logics S4 and S5 (cf. [[Modal logic|Modal logic]]): | ||
− | + | $$ | |
+ | \textrm{ If } \Gamma , A \vdash B,\ \textrm{ then } \ | ||
+ | \Gamma \vdash ( \square A \supset B ) . | ||
+ | $$ | ||
− | More precise formulations of deduction theorems are obtained if one introduces | + | More precise formulations of deduction theorems are obtained if one introduces $ \forall $- |
+ | quantifiers not over all the free variables, but only over those bounded by quantifiers in the course of the deduction. One says that a variable $ y $ | ||
+ | is varied for a formula $ A $ | ||
+ | in a given deduction if $ y $ | ||
+ | is free in $ A $ | ||
+ | and if the deduction under consideration involves an application of the rule of $ \forall $- | ||
+ | introduction into the conclusion of an implication (or the $ \exists $- | ||
+ | introduction into a premise), in which the quantifier over $ y $ | ||
+ | is introduced, and the premise of the application depends on $ A $ | ||
+ | in the proof under consideration. A deduction theorem for traditional predicate calculus may now be rendered more precise as follows: | ||
− | + | $$ | |
+ | \textrm{ If } \Gamma , A \vdash B,\ \textrm{ then } \ | ||
+ | \Gamma \vdash ( \forall y _ {1} \dots y _ {n} A \supset B ) , | ||
+ | $$ | ||
− | where | + | where $ y _ {1} \dots y _ {n} $ |
+ | is the complete list of variables varied for $ A $ | ||
+ | in the deduction under consideration. In particular, if no free variable in $ A $ | ||
+ | is varied, a deduction theorem assumes the form (*). In formulating the appropriate refinements of a deduction theorem for modal logics it should be borne in mind that the variation takes place in the rules for the introduction of $ \square $ | ||
+ | into the conclusion of the implication and $ \dia $ | ||
+ | into the premise. | ||
− | In establishing a deduction theorem for the calculus of relevant implication (i.e. for systems adapted to the interpretation of | + | In establishing a deduction theorem for the calculus of relevant implication (i.e. for systems adapted to the interpretation of $ A \supset B $ |
+ | as "B is deducible with essential use of assumption A" ) one has the alternative of modifying the concept of the deduction itself or else of assuming that the variation takes place in any use of a "secondary" assumption; for instance, on passing from the pair $ A , \Gamma \vdash C $, | ||
+ | $ \Gamma \vdash D $ | ||
+ | to $ A , \Gamma \vdash ( C \& D) $, | ||
+ | formula $ A $ | ||
+ | is varied, since it does not form part of the second member of the pair. | ||
− | If, in a given deduction, | + | If, in a given deduction, $ A $ |
+ | is not varied, a deduction theorem assumes the form (*), and if $ A $ | ||
+ | is varied it takes the following form: | ||
− | + | $$ | |
+ | \textrm{ If } A, \Gamma \vdash B,\ \textrm{ then } \ | ||
+ | \Gamma \vdash (( A \& t ) \supset B ) , | ||
+ | $$ | ||
− | where | + | where $ t $ |
+ | is a "true" constant (or the conjunction of the formulas $ ( p \supset p) $ | ||
+ | for all propositional variables $ p $ | ||
+ | in $ A $, | ||
+ | $ \Gamma $, | ||
+ | $ B $). | ||
====References==== | ====References==== | ||
<table><TR><TD valign="top">[1]</TD> <TD valign="top"> S.C. Kleene, "Introduction to metamathematics" , North-Holland (1951)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[2]</TD> <TD valign="top"> H.B. Curry, "Foundations of mathematical logic" , McGraw-Hill (1963)</TD></TR></table> | <table><TR><TD valign="top">[1]</TD> <TD valign="top"> S.C. Kleene, "Introduction to metamathematics" , North-Holland (1951)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[2]</TD> <TD valign="top"> H.B. Curry, "Foundations of mathematical logic" , McGraw-Hill (1963)</TD></TR></table> | ||
− | |||
− | |||
====Comments==== | ====Comments==== | ||
− | |||
====References==== | ====References==== | ||
<table><TR><TD valign="top">[a1]</TD> <TD valign="top"> A. Grzegorczyk, "An outline of mathematical logic" , Reidel (1974)</TD></TR></table> | <table><TR><TD valign="top">[a1]</TD> <TD valign="top"> A. Grzegorczyk, "An outline of mathematical logic" , Reidel (1974)</TD></TR></table> |
Latest revision as of 17:32, 5 June 2020
A general term for a number of theorems which allow one to establish that the implication $ A \supset B $
can be proved if it is possible to deduce logically formula $ B $
from formula $ A $.
In the simplest case of classical, intuitionistic, etc., propositional calculus, a deduction theorem states the following: If $ \Gamma , A \vdash B $(
$ B $
is deducible from the assumptions $ \Gamma , A $),
then
$$ \tag{* } \Gamma \vdash ( A \supset B ) $$
( $ \Gamma $ may be empty). In the presence of quantifiers an analogous statement is false:
$$ A ( x) \vdash \forall x A ( x) , $$
but not
$$ \vdash A ( x) \supset \forall x A ( x) . $$
One of the formulations of a deduction theorem for traditional (classical, intuitionistic, etc.) predicate calculus is: If $ \Gamma , A \vdash B $, then
$$ \Gamma \vdash ( \forall A \supset B ) , $$
where $ \forall A $ is the result of prefixing $ \forall $ quantifiers (cf. Quantifier) over all the free variables of the formula $ A $. In particular, if $ A $ is a closed formula, a deduction theorem assumes the form (*). This formulation of a deduction theorem makes it possible to reduce proof search in axiomatic theories to proof search in predicate calculus: Formula $ B $ is deducible from axioms $ A _ {1} \dots A _ {n} $ if and only if the formula
$$ \forall A _ {1} \supset ( \forall A _ {2} \supset \dots \supset ( \forall A _ {n} \supset B ) \dots ) $$
is deducible in predicate calculus.
A deduction theorem is formulated in a similar manner for logics with operations "resembling" quantifiers. Thus, a deduction theorem has the following form for the modal logics S4 and S5 (cf. Modal logic):
$$ \textrm{ If } \Gamma , A \vdash B,\ \textrm{ then } \ \Gamma \vdash ( \square A \supset B ) . $$
More precise formulations of deduction theorems are obtained if one introduces $ \forall $- quantifiers not over all the free variables, but only over those bounded by quantifiers in the course of the deduction. One says that a variable $ y $ is varied for a formula $ A $ in a given deduction if $ y $ is free in $ A $ and if the deduction under consideration involves an application of the rule of $ \forall $- introduction into the conclusion of an implication (or the $ \exists $- introduction into a premise), in which the quantifier over $ y $ is introduced, and the premise of the application depends on $ A $ in the proof under consideration. A deduction theorem for traditional predicate calculus may now be rendered more precise as follows:
$$ \textrm{ If } \Gamma , A \vdash B,\ \textrm{ then } \ \Gamma \vdash ( \forall y _ {1} \dots y _ {n} A \supset B ) , $$
where $ y _ {1} \dots y _ {n} $ is the complete list of variables varied for $ A $ in the deduction under consideration. In particular, if no free variable in $ A $ is varied, a deduction theorem assumes the form (*). In formulating the appropriate refinements of a deduction theorem for modal logics it should be borne in mind that the variation takes place in the rules for the introduction of $ \square $ into the conclusion of the implication and $ \dia $ into the premise.
In establishing a deduction theorem for the calculus of relevant implication (i.e. for systems adapted to the interpretation of $ A \supset B $ as "B is deducible with essential use of assumption A" ) one has the alternative of modifying the concept of the deduction itself or else of assuming that the variation takes place in any use of a "secondary" assumption; for instance, on passing from the pair $ A , \Gamma \vdash C $, $ \Gamma \vdash D $ to $ A , \Gamma \vdash ( C \& D) $, formula $ A $ is varied, since it does not form part of the second member of the pair.
If, in a given deduction, $ A $ is not varied, a deduction theorem assumes the form (*), and if $ A $ is varied it takes the following form:
$$ \textrm{ If } A, \Gamma \vdash B,\ \textrm{ then } \ \Gamma \vdash (( A \& t ) \supset B ) , $$
where $ t $ is a "true" constant (or the conjunction of the formulas $ ( p \supset p) $ for all propositional variables $ p $ in $ A $, $ \Gamma $, $ B $).
References
[1] | S.C. Kleene, "Introduction to metamathematics" , North-Holland (1951) |
[2] | H.B. Curry, "Foundations of mathematical logic" , McGraw-Hill (1963) |
Comments
References
[a1] | A. Grzegorczyk, "An outline of mathematical logic" , Reidel (1974) |
Deduction theorem. Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=Deduction_theorem&oldid=17084