Difference between revisions of "Utility theory"
(Importing text file) |
(LaTeX) |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
− | A theory dealing with individual preferences and the representation of these by numerical functions. A preference relation on a set of alternatives | + | A theory dealing with individual preferences and the representation of these by numerical functions. A preference relation on a set of alternatives $X$ is a complete transitive binary relation $R$ on $X$; it is represented by a function $u(x)$ on $X$, and $u(x)$ is called a utility function if for any $x,y \in X$ it follows from $x R y$ that $u(x) \ge u(y)$, and vice versa. Therefore utility theory deals with ordered sets and their monotone mappings into a numerical space (usually one-dimensional). Utility theory arose from researches by economists in the 18th century; the basis of modern utility theory was laid in the 1940s by J. von Neumann and O. Morgenstern [[#References|[1]]]. |
− | It is obvious that a utility function exists in the case of a finite set | + | It is obvious that a utility function exists in the case of a finite set $X$. In the infinite case, a necessary and sufficient condition for the existence of a utility function is the existence of a utility-dense countable subset $A \subset X$, i.e. for any $x,y \in X \setminus A$ such that $x R^* y$, there exists a $z \in A$ such that $x R^* z$ and $z R^* y$, where $R^*$ is a strong preference relation ($x R^* y \Leftrightarrow x R y$ and not $y R x$). If $X$ is a convex set in a vector space, $R$ is continuous on $X$ and for any $x,y,z \in X$, $x R^* y$, and any $\alpha$, $0 < \alpha < 1$, it is true that $[\alpha x + (1-\alpha)z] R^* [\alpha y + (1-\alpha)z]$, then there exists a linear utility function that is unique, up to a positive linear transformation [[#References|[3]]]. Various combinations of weaker conditions lead to non-linear, discontinuous, or in some sense non-unique, utility functions. For example, if $X$ is a vector space, if it follows from $x R^* y$ that $x+z R^* y+z$ and if $\alpha x R^* \alpha y$ for all $z \in X$ and $\alpha > 0$, the function is single-valued and piecewise linear. |
− | Utility theory also deals with stochastic ordering and ordering of the sums or differences of alternatives (in that case the utility function is constructed from a certain quaternary relation on | + | Utility theory also deals with stochastic ordering and ordering of the sums or differences of alternatives (in that case the utility function is constructed from a certain quaternary relation on $X$), as well as with generalizations to $n$-ary relations instead of binary ones, with the construction of a utility function at the same time with subjective probabilities, with the relation between the utility of multi-component alternatives and the utilities of the components, etc., [[#References|[3]]], [[#References|[4]]]. |
====References==== | ====References==== | ||
− | <table><TR><TD valign="top">[1]</TD> <TD valign="top"> J. von Neumann, O. Morgenstern, "Theory of games and economic behavior" , Princeton Univ. Press (1947)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[2]</TD> <TD valign="top"> G. Birkhoff, "Lattice theory" , ''Colloq. Publ.'' , '''25''' , Amer. Math. Soc. (1973)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[3]</TD> <TD valign="top"> P.S. Fishburn, "Utility theory for decision making" , Wiley (1970)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[4]</TD> <TD valign="top"> P. Suppes, J. Zines, "Psychological measurements" , Moscow (1967) (In Russian; translated from English)</TD></TR></table> | + | <table> |
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[1]</TD> <TD valign="top"> J. von Neumann, O. Morgenstern, "Theory of games and economic behavior" , Princeton Univ. Press (1947)</TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[2]</TD> <TD valign="top"> G. Birkhoff, "Lattice theory" , ''Colloq. Publ.'' , '''25''' , Amer. Math. Soc. (1973)</TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[3]</TD> <TD valign="top"> P.S. Fishburn, "Utility theory for decision making" , Wiley (1970)</TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[4]</TD> <TD valign="top"> P. Suppes, J. Zines, "Psychological measurements" , Moscow (1967) (In Russian; translated from English)</TD></TR> | ||
+ | </table> | ||
Line 14: | Line 19: | ||
====References==== | ====References==== | ||
− | <table><TR><TD valign="top">[a1]</TD> <TD valign="top"> R.J. Aumann, , ''Human Judgement and Optimality'' , Wiley (1964) pp. 217–242</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a2]</TD> <TD valign="top"> Y. Kannai, "The ALEP definition of complementary and least concave utility functions" ''J. Economic Th.'' , '''22''' (1980) pp. 115–117</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a3]</TD> <TD valign="top"> Y. Kannai, , ''Generalized Concavity in Optimization and Economics'' , Acad. Press (1981) pp. 543–611</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a4]</TD> <TD valign="top"> R.D. Luce, H. Raiffa, "Games and decisions. Introduction and critical survey" , Wiley (1957)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a5]</TD> <TD valign="top"> P.A. Samuelson, "Foundations of economic analysis" , Harvard Univ. Press (1947)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a6]</TD> <TD valign="top"> P.A. Samuelson, ''J. Economic Literature'' , '''12''' (1974) pp. 1255–1289</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a7]</TD> <TD valign="top"> H. Skala, "Nonstandard utilities and the foundations of game theory" ''Internat. J. Game Theory'' , '''3''' (1974) pp. 67–81</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a8]</TD> <TD valign="top"> R.M. Thrall (ed.) C.H. Coombs (ed.) R.L. Davis (ed.) , ''Decision processes'' , Wiley (1954)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a9]</TD> <TD valign="top"> K.J. Arrow, F.H. Hahn, "General competitive analysis" , Oliver & Boyd (1971)</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a10]</TD> <TD valign="top"> G. Debreu, "Continuity properties of Paretian utility" ''Int. Econ. Review'' , '''5''' (1964) pp. 285–293</TD></TR><TR><TD valign="top">[a11]</TD> <TD valign="top"> J.T. Rader, "The existence of a utility function to represent preferences" ''Rev. of Econ. Studies'' , '''XXX''' (1963) pp. 229–232</TD></TR></table> | + | <table> |
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[a1]</TD> <TD valign="top"> R.J. Aumann, , ''Human Judgement and Optimality'' , Wiley (1964) pp. 217–242</TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[a2]</TD> <TD valign="top"> Y. Kannai, "The ALEP definition of complementary and least concave utility functions" ''J. Economic Th.'' , '''22''' (1980) pp. 115–117</TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[a3]</TD> <TD valign="top"> Y. Kannai, , ''Generalized Concavity in Optimization and Economics'' , Acad. Press (1981) pp. 543–611</TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[a4]</TD> <TD valign="top"> R.D. Luce, H. Raiffa, "Games and decisions. Introduction and critical survey" , Wiley (1957)</TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[a5]</TD> <TD valign="top"> P.A. Samuelson, "Foundations of economic analysis" , Harvard Univ. Press (1947)</TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[a6]</TD> <TD valign="top"> P.A. Samuelson, ''J. Economic Literature'' , '''12''' (1974) pp. 1255–1289</TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[a7]</TD> <TD valign="top"> H. Skala, "Nonstandard utilities and the foundations of game theory" ''Internat. J. Game Theory'' , '''3''' (1974) pp. 67–81</TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[a8]</TD> <TD valign="top"> R.M. Thrall (ed.) C.H. Coombs (ed.) R.L. Davis (ed.) , ''Decision processes'' , Wiley (1954)</TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[a9]</TD> <TD valign="top"> K.J. Arrow, F.H. Hahn, "General competitive analysis" , Oliver & Boyd (1971)</TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[a10]</TD> <TD valign="top"> G. Debreu, "Continuity properties of Paretian utility" ''Int. Econ. Review'' , '''5''' (1964) pp. 285–293</TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[a11]</TD> <TD valign="top"> J.T. Rader, "The existence of a utility function to represent preferences" ''Rev. of Econ. Studies'' , '''XXX''' (1963) pp. 229–232</TD></TR> | ||
+ | </table> | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{TEX|done}} |
Revision as of 18:41, 17 October 2014
A theory dealing with individual preferences and the representation of these by numerical functions. A preference relation on a set of alternatives $X$ is a complete transitive binary relation $R$ on $X$; it is represented by a function $u(x)$ on $X$, and $u(x)$ is called a utility function if for any $x,y \in X$ it follows from $x R y$ that $u(x) \ge u(y)$, and vice versa. Therefore utility theory deals with ordered sets and their monotone mappings into a numerical space (usually one-dimensional). Utility theory arose from researches by economists in the 18th century; the basis of modern utility theory was laid in the 1940s by J. von Neumann and O. Morgenstern [1].
It is obvious that a utility function exists in the case of a finite set $X$. In the infinite case, a necessary and sufficient condition for the existence of a utility function is the existence of a utility-dense countable subset $A \subset X$, i.e. for any $x,y \in X \setminus A$ such that $x R^* y$, there exists a $z \in A$ such that $x R^* z$ and $z R^* y$, where $R^*$ is a strong preference relation ($x R^* y \Leftrightarrow x R y$ and not $y R x$). If $X$ is a convex set in a vector space, $R$ is continuous on $X$ and for any $x,y,z \in X$, $x R^* y$, and any $\alpha$, $0 < \alpha < 1$, it is true that $[\alpha x + (1-\alpha)z] R^* [\alpha y + (1-\alpha)z]$, then there exists a linear utility function that is unique, up to a positive linear transformation [3]. Various combinations of weaker conditions lead to non-linear, discontinuous, or in some sense non-unique, utility functions. For example, if $X$ is a vector space, if it follows from $x R^* y$ that $x+z R^* y+z$ and if $\alpha x R^* \alpha y$ for all $z \in X$ and $\alpha > 0$, the function is single-valued and piecewise linear.
Utility theory also deals with stochastic ordering and ordering of the sums or differences of alternatives (in that case the utility function is constructed from a certain quaternary relation on $X$), as well as with generalizations to $n$-ary relations instead of binary ones, with the construction of a utility function at the same time with subjective probabilities, with the relation between the utility of multi-component alternatives and the utilities of the components, etc., [3], [4].
References
[1] | J. von Neumann, O. Morgenstern, "Theory of games and economic behavior" , Princeton Univ. Press (1947) |
[2] | G. Birkhoff, "Lattice theory" , Colloq. Publ. , 25 , Amer. Math. Soc. (1973) |
[3] | P.S. Fishburn, "Utility theory for decision making" , Wiley (1970) |
[4] | P. Suppes, J. Zines, "Psychological measurements" , Moscow (1967) (In Russian; translated from English) |
Comments
Among other aspects of utility theory, one might mention transferable utility [a4], incomplete preferences [a1], non-standard utilities [a7], as well as the large body of literature concerning the (non-) significance of utility representations for economic theory (see, e.g., [a5] and [a6], but in the special case of concavifiable preference orderings one gets some measure of cardinal utility functions [a2], [a3]).
References
[a1] | R.J. Aumann, , Human Judgement and Optimality , Wiley (1964) pp. 217–242 |
[a2] | Y. Kannai, "The ALEP definition of complementary and least concave utility functions" J. Economic Th. , 22 (1980) pp. 115–117 |
[a3] | Y. Kannai, , Generalized Concavity in Optimization and Economics , Acad. Press (1981) pp. 543–611 |
[a4] | R.D. Luce, H. Raiffa, "Games and decisions. Introduction and critical survey" , Wiley (1957) |
[a5] | P.A. Samuelson, "Foundations of economic analysis" , Harvard Univ. Press (1947) |
[a6] | P.A. Samuelson, J. Economic Literature , 12 (1974) pp. 1255–1289 |
[a7] | H. Skala, "Nonstandard utilities and the foundations of game theory" Internat. J. Game Theory , 3 (1974) pp. 67–81 |
[a8] | R.M. Thrall (ed.) C.H. Coombs (ed.) R.L. Davis (ed.) , Decision processes , Wiley (1954) |
[a9] | K.J. Arrow, F.H. Hahn, "General competitive analysis" , Oliver & Boyd (1971) |
[a10] | G. Debreu, "Continuity properties of Paretian utility" Int. Econ. Review , 5 (1964) pp. 285–293 |
[a11] | J.T. Rader, "The existence of a utility function to represent preferences" Rev. of Econ. Studies , XXX (1963) pp. 229–232 |
Utility theory. Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=Utility_theory&oldid=17247