Namespaces
Variants
Actions

Difference between revisions of "User:Whayes43"

From Encyclopedia of Mathematics
Jump to: navigation, search
Line 47: Line 47:
 
::consisting of axioms
 
::consisting of axioms
 
::::$Sx\neq 0$ and $Sx = Sy \to x = y$
 
::::$Sx\neq 0$ and $Sx = Sy \to x = y$
::defining equalities for
+
::defining equalities for $+$ and $\cdot$
::::$+$ and $\cdot$
+
::::$x + 0 = x$ and $x + Sx = S(x + y)$
 +
::::$x \cdot 0 = 0$ and $x \cdot S(y) = x \cdot y + x$
 
::and with the induction scheme
 
::and with the induction scheme
 
::::$A (0) \wedge \forall x (A(x) \to A(Sx)) \to \forall x A(x)$
 
::::$A (0) \wedge \forall x (A(x) \to A(Sx)) \to \forall x A(x)$

Revision as of 15:49, 12 June 2015

A system of five axioms for the set of natural numbers $\mathbb{N}$ and a function $S$ (successor) on it, introduced by G. Peano (1889):

  1. $0 \in \mathbb{N}$
  2. $x \in \mathbb{N} \to Sx \in \mathbb{n}$
  3. $x \in \mathbb{N} \to Sx \neq 0$
  4. $x \in \mathbb{N} \wedge y \in \mathbb{N} \wedge Sx =Sy \to x = y$
  5. $0 \in M \wedge \forall x (x\in M \to Sx\in M) \to \mathbb{N} \subseteq M$ for any property $M$ (axiom of induction).

In the first version of his system, Peano used $1$ instead of $0$ in axioms 1, 3, and 5. Similar axioms were proposed by R. Dedekind (1888).

In the Peano axioms presented above, the axiom of induction (axiom 5) is a statement in second-order language. Dedekind proved that all systems of Peano axioms with such a second-order axiom of induction are categorical. That is, any two systems and satisfying them are isomorphic. The isomorphism is determined by a function , where

The existence of for all pairs and the mutual single-valuedness for are proved by induction.

Peano's axioms make it possible to develop number theory and, in particular, to introduce the usual arithmetic functions and to establish their properties.

All the axioms are independent, but

and

can be combined to a single one:

if one defines as

The independence of Peano’s axioms is proved by exhibiting, for each axiom, a model for which the axiom considered is false, but for which all the other axioms are true. For example:

  • for axiom 1, such a model is the set of natural numbers beginning with $1$
  • for axiom 2, it is the set $\mathbb{N} \cup \{1/2\}$, with $S0 = 1/2$ and $S1/2 =1$
  • for axiom 3, it is the set $\{0\}$
  • for axiom 4, it is the set $\{0, 1\}$, with $S0 = S1 = 1$
  • for axiom 5, it is the set $\mathbb{N} \cup \{-1\}$

Using this method, Peano provided a proof of independence for his axioms (1891).

Sometimes one understands by the term Peano arithmetic the system in the first-order language

with the function symbols
$S, +, \cdot$, ::consisting of axioms ::::$Sx\neq 0$ and $Sx = Sy \to x = y$ ::defining equalities for $+$ and $\cdot$ ::::$x + 0 = x$ and $x + Sx = S(x + y)$ ::::$x \cdot 0 = 0$ and $x \cdot S(y) = x \cdot y + x$ ::and with the induction scheme ::::$A (0) \wedge \forall x (A(x) \to A(Sx)) \to \forall x A(x)$ where $A$ is an arbitrary formula, known as the induction formula (see Arithmetic, formal).

References

  • S.C. Kleene, Introduction to Metamathematics, North-Holland (1951).

Comments

The system of Peano arithmetic in first-order language, mentioned at the end of the article, is no longer categorical (cf. also Categoric system of axioms), and gives rise to so-called non-standard models of arithmetic.

References

  • H.C. Kennedy, ‘’Peano. Life and works of Giuseppe Peano’’, Reidel (1980).
  • H.C. Kennedy, ‘’Selected works of Giuseppe Peano’’, Allen & Unwin (1973).
  • E. Landau, ‘’Grundlagen der Analysis’’, Akad. Verlagsgesellschaft (1930).
How to Cite This Entry:
Whayes43. Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=Whayes43&oldid=36480