Namespaces
Variants
Actions

Difference between revisions of "User:Whayes43"

From Encyclopedia of Mathematics
Jump to: navigation, search
Line 1: Line 1:
===Frege’s theory of arithmetic===
+
===Dedekind’s theory of numbers===
  
Frege, by virtue of his work creating predicate logic, is one of the founders of modern (mathematical) logic. His view was that mathematics is reducible to logic. His major works published with the goal of doing this are these:<ref>O’Connor and Robertson (2002)</ref>
+
Dedekind’s set theory is equivalent to Peirce’s and, consequently, so is his theory of numbers. This equivalence of Peirce’s theory of natural numbers to that of Dedekind (as well as that of Giuseppe Peano’s 1889 Arithmetices principia [60]) was demonstrated by Shields (in [93] and [94]).<ref>Anellis (2012?) p. 260</ref>
* in 1879 -- ''Begriffsschrift'', defining his “axiomatic-deductive” predicate calculus for the ultimate purpose of proving the basic truths of arithmetic "by means of pure logic."
 
* in 1884 -- ''Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik'', using his predicate calculus to present an axiomatic theory of arithmetic.
 
* in 1893/1903 -- ''Die Grundgesetze der Arithmetik'', presenting formal proofs of number theory from an intuitive collection of axioms.
 
  
As we have seen, Boole’s developed his algebra of logic as a means by which ''deduction becomes calculation''. Frege's predicate calculus in the ''Begriffsschrift'' stood Boole’s purpose on its head:<ref>Gillies pp. 74-75</ref>
+
There are only two significant differences between the development of number theory by Dedekind and by Pierce:<ref>Anellis (2012?) p. 259</ref>
* Frege’s goal: “to establish ... that arithmetic could be reduced to logic” and, thus, to create a logic by means of which ''calculation becomes deduction''
+
* Dedekind started from infinite sets rather than finite sets in defining natural numbers
* Frege’s program: to develop arithmetic as an axiomatic system such that all the axioms were truths of logic
+
* Dedekind is explicitly and specifically concerned with the real number continuum, that is, with infinite sets.
  
Driven by “an over-ruling passion to demonstrate his position conclusively” and not “content with the usual informal mathematical standard of rigour,” Frege’s exposition in ''Grundgesetze'' is characterized by a great degree by precision and explicitness.<ref>Azzano p. 12</ref> He himself tells us why this is so:<ref>Frege (1884) cited in Demopoulos p. 7</ref>
+
Frege and Dedekind were focused on “reducing” the natural numbers and arithmetic to “logic”. This is the main goal of Dedekind's ''Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?''
::[T]he fundamental propositions of arithmetic should be proved…with the utmost rigour; for only if every gap in the chain of deductions is eliminated with the greatest care can we say with certainty upon what primitive truths the proof depend.
 
  
Frege gave the following reason for developing his logic as an axiomatic system:<ref>Frege (1879) p. 136 cited in Gillies p. 71 emphasis added</ref>
+
The technical centerpiece of Dedekind’s mathematical work was in number theory, especially algebraic number theory. His primary motivation was to provide a foundation for mathematics and in particular to find a rigorous definition of real numbers and of the real-number continuum upon which to establish mathematical analysis in the style of Karl Weierstrass. This means that he sought to axiomatize the theory of numbers based upon that rigorous definition of the real numbers and the construction of the real number system and the continuum which could be employed in defining the theory of limits of a function for use in the differential and integral calculus, real analysis, and related areas of function theory. His concern, in short, was with the rigorization and arithmetization of analysis.<ref>Anellis (2012?) p. 260</ref>
::Because we cannot enumerate all of the boundless number of laws that can be established, we can obtain completeness only by a search for those [laws] which, potentially, imply all the others.
 
  
Frege also commented on the role of proof in mathematics:<ref>Frege (1884) § 2 cited in ”Philosophical Summaries” emphasis added</ref>
 
::The aim of proof is not merely to place the truth of a proposition beyond all doubt, but also to afford us insight into the dependence of truths upon one another.
 
  
Frege identified as the ''kernel'' of his system the axioms (laws) of his logic that potentially imply all the other laws. His statements above imply that he thought his system to be complete and his axioms to be independent. He did not, however, provide a precise definition of completeness and independence nor did he attempt a proof that his system was complete and his axioms independent.
+
One goal of Dedekind’s of ''Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?'' was to answer the question, What more can be said about the set-theoretic procedures used? For Dedekind, again like for Frege, these procedures are founded in “logic”. But then, what are the basic notions of logic?<ref>SEP</ref>
  
Early in his first book on the foundations of arithmetic, Frege established his purpose:<ref>Frege (1884) § 4 cited in Demopoulos p. 5 emphasis added</ref>
+
* ‘’Ordinal numbers’’ are used to count elements and place them in a succession; in such cases they correspond to Enligsh expressions such as first, second, third... and so forth.
::[I]t is above all $Number$ which has to be either defined or recognized as indefinable. This is the point which the present work is meant to settle.
+
* ‘’Cardinal numbers’’ are used, loosely speaking, to count how many elements of some kind there are: one cat, two dogs, three horses, and so forth.
 +
For Dedekind, numbers are essentially ordinals.<ref>Azzano p. 16</ref>
  
Frege began the introduction of numbers into his logic by defining what is meant by saying that two $Numbers$ are equal:<ref>Frege (1884) cited in Gillies p. 46-48</ref><ref>Frege (1884) cited in Dietz</ref>
+
Dedekind’s efforts in foundations did not stop with the reduction of all mathematics to arithmetic, thinking that both the concepts and the rules of arithmetic itself needed clarification -- principally through logic and set theory.<ref>Azzano p. 8</ref>
::two concepts $F$ and $G$ are equal if the things that fall under them can be put into one-one correspondence
 
From this he arrives at the notion that “a $Number$ is a set of concepts”:
 
* §72 the $Number$ that belongs to the concept $F$ is the extension of the concept “equal to the concept $F$”
 
:and then continues as follows by defining the expression
 
::::$n$ is a $Number$
 
:to mean
 
::::there exists a concept such that $n$ is the $Number$ that belongs to it.
 
* §73 he draws this inference
 
::::the concept $F$ is equal to the concept $G$
 
:implies
 
::::the $Number$ belonging to the concept $F$ is identical to the $Number$ belonging to the concept $G$
 
* §74 he defines the $Number$ $0$ as
 
::::the $Number$ that belongs to the concept “not identical with itself”
 
* §75 he immediately clarifies this, stating
 
::::Every concept under which no object falls is equal to every other concept under which no object falls, and to them alone.
 
:and therefore
 
::::$0$ is the $Number$ which belongs to any such concept, and no object falls under any concept if the number which belongs to that concept is $0$.
 
* §76 he defines the $Successor$ relation
 
::::$n$ follows in the series of $Numbers$ directly after $m$
 
:to mean
 
::::there exists a concept $F$ and an object falling under it, $x$, such that
 
::::::the $Number$ belonging to the concept $F$ is $n$
 
::::and
 
::::::the $Number$ belonging to the concept “falling under $F$ but not equal to $x$” is $m$
 
* §77 he defines the $Number$ $1$ as
 
::::“the $Number$ belonging to the concept ‘identical with $0$’”
 
:from which it follows that
 
::::$1$ is the $Number$ that follows directly after $0$
 
* §78-81 he proves or gives a proof sketch for several propositions regarding the $Successor$ relation, using definitions of $series$ and $following$ $in$ $a$ $series$ from his earlier work of 1879
 
::* the $Successor$ relation is 1-1
 
::* every $Number$ except $0$ is a $Successor$
 
::* every $Number$ has a $Successor$
 
* §82 he outlines a proof that there is no last member in the series of $Numbers$
 
* §83 he provides a definition of finite Number, noting that no finite Number follows in the series of natural numbers after itself
 
* §84 he notes that the $Number$ which belongs to the concept 'finite N$umber$' is an infinite $Number$.  
 
  
Central to all of this work was a distinction that Frege was developing, but only finally published in 1892 and incorporated in the ''Grundgesetze'', namely, that every concept, mathematical or otherwise, had two important, entirely distinct aspects:<ref>Frege (1892)</ref><ref>Gillies p. 83</ref>
+
The ultimate basis of a mathematician’s knowledge is, according to Dedekind, the clarification of the concept of natural numbers (viz., positive integers) in a non-mathematical fashion, which involves this twofold task:<ref>Gillies cited in Azzano p. 5</ref>
# ''Sinn'': a “meaning” or “sense” or “connotation”
+
# to define numerical concepts (natural numbers) through logical ones
# ''Bedeutung'': an “extension” or “reference” or “denotation”
+
# to characterize mathematical induction (the passage from n to n+1) as a logical inference.
  
This distinction of Frege's is the basis of what Gödel (many years later) characterized as the ''dichotomic conception'':<ref>Ferreiros pp. 18-19</ref>
 
::Any well-defined concept (property or predicate) $P(x)$ establishes a dichotomy of all things into those that are $P$s and those that are non-$P$s.
 
:In other words,
 
::a concept partitions $V$ (the universe of discourse) into two classes: the class $\{ x : P(x) \}$ and its absolute complement, the class $\{ x : \neg P(x) \}$.
 
Underlying this notion are two key assumptions:
 
# the existence of a ''Universal Set'', $V$ -- what we have seen as Dedekind’s ''Gedankenwelt''
 
# the unrestricted principle of ''Comprehension'' -- ''any'' well-defined property determines, a set.
 
For “naïve” set theory, these two assumptions are equivalent and either one of them suffices to derive the other:
 
* to derive ''Universal Set'' from ''Comprehension'':
 
::::replace $Φ(x)$ by a truism, such as the property $x = x$.
 
* to derive ''Comprehension'' from the ''Universal Set'':
 
::assume an all-encompassing set $V$,
 
::::note that any part of $V$ is also a set,
 
::::and that any well-defined concept $P(x)$ defines a subset of $V$,
 
::therefore the set $\{ x : P(x) \}$ exists!
 
To these two assumptions, add Dedekind's principle of ''Extensionality''.
 
  
Frege intended the ''Grundgesetze'' to be the implementation of his program to demonstrate “every proposition of arithmetic” to be ”a [derivative] law of logic.” In this work of 19 years duration, there was no explicit appeal to an ''unrestricted'' principle of Comprehension. Instead, Frege's theory of arithmetic appealed to Comprehension by virtue of its symbolism, according to which for any predicate $Φ(x)$ (concept or property) one can form an expression $S = \{ x : Φ(x)\}$ defining a set. Frege's theory assumes that (somehow) there is a mapping which associates an object (a set of objects) to every concept, but he does not present comprehension as an explicit assumption. All of this is in contrast to the use of ''restricted'' predicates in Cantor's early theory of sets.<ref>Azzano p. 10</ref><ref>Ferreiros pp. 18-19. Ferreiros notes (with surprise) that, in spite of its importance to naive set theory, the unrestricted principle of Comprehension was almost nowhere stated clearly before it was proved to be contradictory!</ref>
 
  
==Notes==
+
Dedekind’s methods led him to develop a “set-theoretic” style of axiomatic analysis that is quite different from the work of Peano on the natural numbers, or that of Hilbert on geometry and the real numbers…. To clarify the matter, let me remind you of Dedekind’s axioms:
 +
::A simply infinite set $N$ has a distinguished element $e$ and an ordering mapping $ϕ$ such that
 +
::# $ϕ(N) ⊆ N$
 +
::# $e \notin ϕ(N)$
 +
::# $N = ϕ0(e)$, i.e. $N$ is the $ϕ-chain of the unitary set $\{e\}$
 +
::# $ϕ$ is an injective mapping from $N$ to $N$, i.e. if $ϕ(a) = ϕ(b)$ then $a = b$.
 +
Leaving aside axioms 2. and 4., which are more easy to assimilate to Peano’s axioms, the other two axioms are characteristically set-theoretic in the intended sense, and not elementary as most of Peano’s and Hilbert’s axioms.
 +
Peano tended to impose conditions on the behaviour of his individuals, the natural numbers, and the operations on them. These are elementary conditions which most often are amenable to formalization within first-order logic. Dedekind establishes structural conditions on subsets of the (structured) sets he is defining, on the behaviour of relevant maps, or both things at a time. Axiom 1. says that $N$ is closed under the map $ϕ$, Axiom 3. says that $N$ is the minimal closure of the unitary set $\{e\}$ under $ϕ$. Such axioms are non-elementary and tend to require second-order logic for their formalisation<ref>Ferreiros “On Dedekind’s Logicism” p. 19</ref>
  
<references/>
+
A set of objects is infinite—“Dedekind-infinite”, as we now say—if it can be mapped one-to-one onto a proper subset of itself.<ref>Reck (2011) §2.2</ref>
  
==Primary sources==
+
“What are the mutually independent fundamental properties of the sequence N, that is, those properties that are not derivable from one another but from which all others follow? And how should we divest these properties of their specifically arithmetic character so that they are subsumed under more general notions and under activities of the understanding without which no thinking is possible at all, but with which a foundation is provided for the reliability and completeness of proofs and for the construction of consistent notions and definitions.”<ref>Dedekind (1888) pp. 99-100 cited in Awodey and Reck p. 8</ref>
  
* Frege, G. (1879). ''Begriffsschrift ...'', [“Conceptual Notation …”, English translation by T W Bynum, Oxford University Press, 1972].
+
Dedekind's intention was not to axiomatize arithmetic, but to give an "algebraic" characterization of natural numbers as a mathematical structure.<ref>Podnieks § 3.1 From Peano Axioms to First Order Arithmetic</ref>
  
* Frege, G. (1884). ''Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik'', [''The Foundations of Arithmetic'', English translation J L Austin, Basil Blackwell, 1968].
+
What it means to be ‘’simply infinite’’ can be captured in four conditions:<ref>Reck (2011) §2.2</ref>
 +
:Consider a set $S$ and a subset $N$ of $S$ (possibly equal to $S$). Then $N$ is called simply infinite if there exists a function $f$ on $S$ and an element $1$ of $N$ such that
 +
:# $f$ maps $N$ into itself
 +
:# $N$ is the chain of $\{1\}$ in $S$ under $f$
 +
:# $1$ is not in the image of $N$ under $f$
 +
:# $f$ is one-to-one
  
* Frege, G. (1884) ... [Dietz, A. "Frege: The Foundations of Arithmetic (1884)," A brief summary keyed to sections of the original text, URL: https://sites.google.com/site/philosophysummaries/personal/previous-classes/500/frege-the-foundations-of-arithmetic-1884, Accessed: 2015/08/14.]
+
These Dedekindian conditions are a notational variant of the Peano axioms for the natural numbers. In particular, condition 2 is a version of the axiom of mathematical induction. These axioms are thus properly called the Dedekind-Peano axioms.<ref>Reck (2011) §2.2</ref>
  
* Frege, G. (1892) ''Uber Sinn und Bedeuting'', [“On Sense and Reference,” ''Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege'', Geach and Black (eds.) Blackwell, 1960, pp. 56-78].
+
As is also readily apparent, any simple infinity will consist of a first element $1$, a second element $f(1)$, a third $f(f(1))$, then $f(f(f(1)))$, and so on, just like any model of the Dedekind-Peano axioms.<ref>Reck (2011) §2.2</ref>
  
* Frege, G. (1893) ''Grundgesetze'', [''The Basic Laws of Arithmetic'', English translation by M Firth, University of California, 1964].
+
Dedekind introduces the natural numbers as follows:
 +
# he proves that every infinite set contains a simply infinite subset
 +
# he shows, in contemporary terminology, that any two simply infinite systems, or any two models of the Dedekind-Peano axioms, are isomorphic (so that the axiom system is categorical)
 +
# he notes that consequently … any truth about one of them can be translated, via the isomorphism, into a corresponding truth about the other.
  
==References==
+
(As one may put it, all models of the Dedekind-Peano axioms are “logically equivalent”, which means that the axiom system is “semantically complete”; compare Awodey & Reck 2002 and Reck 2003a)
  
* Azzano
+
What Dedekind has introduced, along such lines, is the natural numbers conceived of as finite “ordinal” numbers (or counting numbers: the first, the second, etc.). Later he adds an explanation of how the usual employment of the natural numbers as finite “cardinal” numbers (answering to the question: how many?) can be recovered. This is done by using initial segments of the number series as tallies: for any set we can ask which such segment, if any, can be mapped one-to-one onto it, thus measuring its “cardinality”. (A set turns out to be finite, in the sense defined above, if and only if there exists such an initial segment of the natural numbers series.)<ref>Reck (2011) §2.2</ref>
  
* Ferreiros “Hilbert, Logicism, and Mathematical Existence”
+
==Notes==
  
* Gillies
+
<references/>
 
 
* O’Connor and Robertson
 

Revision as of 23:44, 24 August 2015

Dedekind’s theory of numbers

Dedekind’s set theory is equivalent to Peirce’s and, consequently, so is his theory of numbers. This equivalence of Peirce’s theory of natural numbers to that of Dedekind (as well as that of Giuseppe Peano’s 1889 Arithmetices principia [60]) was demonstrated by Shields (in [93] and [94]).[1]

There are only two significant differences between the development of number theory by Dedekind and by Pierce:[2]

  • Dedekind started from infinite sets rather than finite sets in defining natural numbers
  • Dedekind is explicitly and specifically concerned with the real number continuum, that is, with infinite sets.

Frege and Dedekind were focused on “reducing” the natural numbers and arithmetic to “logic”. This is the main goal of Dedekind's Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?

The technical centerpiece of Dedekind’s mathematical work was in number theory, especially algebraic number theory. His primary motivation was to provide a foundation for mathematics and in particular to find a rigorous definition of real numbers and of the real-number continuum upon which to establish mathematical analysis in the style of Karl Weierstrass. This means that he sought to axiomatize the theory of numbers based upon that rigorous definition of the real numbers and the construction of the real number system and the continuum which could be employed in defining the theory of limits of a function for use in the differential and integral calculus, real analysis, and related areas of function theory. His concern, in short, was with the rigorization and arithmetization of analysis.[3]


One goal of Dedekind’s of Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? was to answer the question, What more can be said about the set-theoretic procedures used? For Dedekind, again like for Frege, these procedures are founded in “logic”. But then, what are the basic notions of logic?[4]

  • ‘’Ordinal numbers’’ are used to count elements and place them in a succession; in such cases they correspond to Enligsh expressions such as first, second, third... and so forth.
  • ‘’Cardinal numbers’’ are used, loosely speaking, to count how many elements of some kind there are: one cat, two dogs, three horses, and so forth.

For Dedekind, numbers are essentially ordinals.[5]

Dedekind’s efforts in foundations did not stop with the reduction of all mathematics to arithmetic, thinking that both the concepts and the rules of arithmetic itself needed clarification -- principally through logic and set theory.[6]

The ultimate basis of a mathematician’s knowledge is, according to Dedekind, the clarification of the concept of natural numbers (viz., positive integers) in a non-mathematical fashion, which involves this twofold task:[7]

  1. to define numerical concepts (natural numbers) through logical ones
  2. to characterize mathematical induction (the passage from n to n+1) as a logical inference.


Dedekind’s methods led him to develop a “set-theoretic” style of axiomatic analysis that is quite different from the work of Peano on the natural numbers, or that of Hilbert on geometry and the real numbers…. To clarify the matter, let me remind you of Dedekind’s axioms:

A simply infinite set $N$ has a distinguished element $e$ and an ordering mapping $ϕ$ such that
  1. $ϕ(N) ⊆ N$
  2. $e \notin ϕ(N)$
  3. $N = ϕ0(e)$, i.e. $N$ is the $ϕ-chain of the unitary set $\{e\}$ ::# $ϕ$ is an injective mapping from $N$ to $N$, i.e. if $ϕ(a) = ϕ(b)$ then $a = b$. Leaving aside axioms 2. and 4., which are more easy to assimilate to Peano’s axioms, the other two axioms are characteristically set-theoretic in the intended sense, and not elementary as most of Peano’s and Hilbert’s axioms. Peano tended to impose conditions on the behaviour of his individuals, the natural numbers, and the operations on them. These are elementary conditions which most often are amenable to formalization within first-order logic. Dedekind establishes structural conditions on subsets of the (structured) sets he is defining, on the behaviour of relevant maps, or both things at a time. Axiom 1. says that $N$ is closed under the map $ϕ$, Axiom 3. says that $N$ is the minimal closure of the unitary set $\{e\}$ under $ϕ$. Such axioms are non-elementary and tend to require second-order logic for their formalisation'"`UNIQ--ref-00000007-QINU`"' A set of objects is infinite—“Dedekind-infinite”, as we now say—if it can be mapped one-to-one onto a proper subset of itself.'"`UNIQ--ref-00000008-QINU`"' “What are the mutually independent fundamental properties of the sequence N, that is, those properties that are not derivable from one another but from which all others follow? And how should we divest these properties of their specifically arithmetic character so that they are subsumed under more general notions and under activities of the understanding without which no thinking is possible at all, but with which a foundation is provided for the reliability and completeness of proofs and for the construction of consistent notions and definitions.”'"`UNIQ--ref-00000009-QINU`"' Dedekind's intention was not to axiomatize arithmetic, but to give an "algebraic" characterization of natural numbers as a mathematical structure.'"`UNIQ--ref-0000000A-QINU`"' What it means to be ‘’simply infinite’’ can be captured in four conditions:'"`UNIQ--ref-0000000B-QINU`"' :Consider a set $S$ and a subset $N$ of $S$ (possibly equal to $S$). Then $N$ is called simply infinite if there exists a function $f$ on $S$ and an element $1$ of $N$ such that :# $f$ maps $N$ into itself :# $N$ is the chain of $\{1\}$ in $S$ under $f$ :# $1$ is not in the image of $N$ under $f$ :# $f$ is one-to-one These Dedekindian conditions are a notational variant of the Peano axioms for the natural numbers. In particular, condition 2 is a version of the axiom of mathematical induction. These axioms are thus properly called the Dedekind-Peano axioms.'"`UNIQ--ref-0000000C-QINU`"' As is also readily apparent, any simple infinity will consist of a first element $1$, a second element $f(1)$, a third $f(f(1))$, then $f(f(f(1)))$, and so on, just like any model of the Dedekind-Peano axioms.[14]

Dedekind introduces the natural numbers as follows:

  1. he proves that every infinite set contains a simply infinite subset
  2. he shows, in contemporary terminology, that any two simply infinite systems, or any two models of the Dedekind-Peano axioms, are isomorphic (so that the axiom system is categorical)
  3. he notes that consequently … any truth about one of them can be translated, via the isomorphism, into a corresponding truth about the other.

(As one may put it, all models of the Dedekind-Peano axioms are “logically equivalent”, which means that the axiom system is “semantically complete”; compare Awodey & Reck 2002 and Reck 2003a)

What Dedekind has introduced, along such lines, is the natural numbers conceived of as finite “ordinal” numbers (or counting numbers: the first, the second, etc.). Later he adds an explanation of how the usual employment of the natural numbers as finite “cardinal” numbers (answering to the question: how many?) can be recovered. This is done by using initial segments of the number series as tallies: for any set we can ask which such segment, if any, can be mapped one-to-one onto it, thus measuring its “cardinality”. (A set turns out to be finite, in the sense defined above, if and only if there exists such an initial segment of the natural numbers series.)[15]

Notes

  1. Anellis (2012?) p. 260
  2. Anellis (2012?) p. 259
  3. Anellis (2012?) p. 260
  4. SEP
  5. Azzano p. 16
  6. Azzano p. 8
  7. Gillies cited in Azzano p. 5
  8. Ferreiros “On Dedekind’s Logicism” p. 19
  9. Reck (2011) §2.2
  10. Dedekind (1888) pp. 99-100 cited in Awodey and Reck p. 8
  11. Podnieks § 3.1 From Peano Axioms to First Order Arithmetic
  12. Reck (2011) §2.2
  13. Reck (2011) §2.2
  14. Reck (2011) §2.2
  15. Reck (2011) §2.2
How to Cite This Entry:
Whayes43. Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=Whayes43&oldid=36648