Difference between revisions of "Characterization theorems for logics"
(Importing text file) |
m (AUTOMATIC EDIT (latexlist): Replaced 2 formulas out of 2 by TEX code with an average confidence of 2.0 and a minimal confidence of 2.0.) |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
+ | <!--This article has been texified automatically. Since there was no Nroff source code for this article, | ||
+ | the semi-automatic procedure described at https://encyclopediaofmath.org/wiki/User:Maximilian_Janisch/latexlist | ||
+ | was used. | ||
+ | If the TeX and formula formatting is correct, please remove this message and the {{TEX|semi-auto}} category. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Out of 2 formulas, 2 were replaced by TEX code.--> | ||
+ | |||
+ | {{TEX|semi-auto}}{{TEX|done}} | ||
First-order logic (cf. also [[Logical calculus|Logical calculus]]) is well-suited for mathematics, e.g.: | First-order logic (cf. also [[Logical calculus|Logical calculus]]) is well-suited for mathematics, e.g.: | ||
Line 17: | Line 25: | ||
Most of the results obtained can be found in [[#References|[a1]]]. Two characterization theorems obtained for other logics are: | Most of the results obtained can be found in [[#References|[a1]]]. Two characterization theorems obtained for other logics are: | ||
− | a) | + | a) $\mathcal{L} _ { \infty \omega}$ is a maximal bounded logic with the Karp property [[#References|[a2]]]; |
− | b) for topological structures, the logic | + | b) for topological structures, the logic $L _ { t }$ of "invariant sentences" is a maximal logic satisfying the compactness theorem and the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem [[#References|[a4]]]. |
====References==== | ====References==== | ||
− | <table>< | + | <table><tr><td valign="top">[a1]</td> <td valign="top"> J. Barwise, S. Feferman, "Model-theoretic logics" , Springer (1985)</td></tr><tr><td valign="top">[a2]</td> <td valign="top"> J. Barwise, "Axioms for abstract model theory" ''Ann. Math. Logic'' , '''7''' (1974) pp. 221–265</td></tr><tr><td valign="top">[a3]</td> <td valign="top"> P. Lindström, "On extensions of elementary logic" ''Theoria'' , '''35''' (1969) pp. 1–11</td></tr><tr><td valign="top">[a4]</td> <td valign="top"> M. Ziegler, "A language for topological structures which satisfies a Lindström-theorem" ''Bull. Amer. Math. Soc.'' , '''82''' (1976) pp. 568–570</td></tr></table> |
Latest revision as of 16:59, 1 July 2020
First-order logic (cf. also Logical calculus) is well-suited for mathematics, e.g.:
1) There is a sound and complete proof calculus (completeness theorem). The decidability of many theories has been proven using the completeness theorem. (Cf. also Completeness (in logic); Sound rule.)
2) There is a system of first-order logical axioms for set theory (e.g., ZFC) that serves as a basis for mathematics.
3) There is a balance between syntax and semantics, e.g., implicitly definable concepts are explicitly definable (Beth's theorem; cf. also Beth definability theorem).
4) Semantic results such as the compactness theorem and the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem are valuable model-theoretic tools and lead to an enrichment of mathematical methods. Mainly in the period from 1950 to 1970, much effort was spent in finding languages which strengthen first-order logic but are still simple enough to yield general principles which are useful in investigating and classifying models. In particular, taking into account the situation for first-order logic, many logicians attempted to find logics satisfying analogues of the theorems mentioned above. However, results due to P. Lindström [a3] limit this search. Or, to state it more positively, Lindström proved the following characterization theorems for first-order logic:
First-order logic is a maximal logic with respect to expressive power satisfying the compactness theorem and the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem.
First-order logic is a maximal logic satisfying the completeness theorem and the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem.
These results were the starting point for investigations trying to order the diversity of extensions of first-order logic, for a systematic study of the relationship between different model-theoretic properties of logics, and for a search for further characterizations theorems for first-order and other logics.
Most of the results obtained can be found in [a1]. Two characterization theorems obtained for other logics are:
a) $\mathcal{L} _ { \infty \omega}$ is a maximal bounded logic with the Karp property [a2];
b) for topological structures, the logic $L _ { t }$ of "invariant sentences" is a maximal logic satisfying the compactness theorem and the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem [a4].
References
[a1] | J. Barwise, S. Feferman, "Model-theoretic logics" , Springer (1985) |
[a2] | J. Barwise, "Axioms for abstract model theory" Ann. Math. Logic , 7 (1974) pp. 221–265 |
[a3] | P. Lindström, "On extensions of elementary logic" Theoria , 35 (1969) pp. 1–11 |
[a4] | M. Ziegler, "A language for topological structures which satisfies a Lindström-theorem" Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. , 82 (1976) pp. 568–570 |
Characterization theorems for logics. Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=Characterization_theorems_for_logics&oldid=18155