Difference between revisions of "Gödel constructive set"
Ulf Rehmann (talk | contribs) m (moved Gödel constructive set to Goedel constructive set: ascii title) |
(anchor (Gödel) constructible universe) |
||
(2 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
''Gödel constructible set, constructible set'' | ''Gödel constructible set, constructible set'' | ||
− | A set | + | A set that arises in the process of constructing sets described below. Let $ X $ be a set and $ R \subseteq X \times X $ a relation on $ X $. Then consider the first-order language $ L(R,X) $ containing (i) a binary predicate symbol $ \underline{R} $ denoting the relation $ R $ and (ii) individual constant symbols denoting the elements of $ X $ (for each $ x \in X $, its corresponding constant symbol is $ \underline{x} $). The statement “the formula $ \phi $ of the language $ L(R,X) $ is valid in the model $ M = (X,R) $” is written as |
+ | $$ | ||
+ | M \models \phi. | ||
+ | $$ | ||
− | + | A set $ Y \subseteq X $ is called “definable” in the model $ M = (X,R) $ (or $ M $-definable) if and only if there exists a formula $ \phi(v) $ of $ L(R,X) $ with one free variable $ v $ such that | |
+ | $$ | ||
+ | \forall x \in X: \quad x \in Y \iff M \models \phi(x). | ||
+ | $$ | ||
− | + | Let $ \operatorname{Def}(M) $ denote the set of all $ M $-definable sets. To each ordinal $ \alpha $ is associated the set $ L_{\alpha} $ that is recursively defined by the relation | |
+ | $$ | ||
+ | L_{\alpha} = \bigcup_{\beta < \alpha} \operatorname{Def} \left( L_{\beta},\in \!\! |_{L_{\beta}} \right), | ||
+ | $$ | ||
+ | where $ \in \!\! |_{L_{\beta}} $ denotes the membership relation restricted to $ L_{\beta} $. Hence, it follows that | ||
+ | \begin{align} | ||
+ | L_{0} & = \varnothing, \\ | ||
+ | L_{1} & = \{ \varnothing \}, \\ | ||
+ | L_{2} & = \{ \varnothing,\{ \varnothing \} \}, \\ | ||
+ | & \vdots \\ | ||
+ | L_{\omega} & = \bigcup_{n < \omega} L_{n}, \\ | ||
+ | & \vdots | ||
+ | \end{align} | ||
− | + | A set $ z $ is called “constructible” if and only if there exists an ordinal $ \alpha $ such that $ z \in L_{\alpha} $. The class of all constructible sets is the '''(Gödel) constructible universe''', denoted by $ L $. In 1938, Kurt Gödel defined $ L $ and introduced the following axiom of constructibility: Every set is constructible. On the basis of the axioms of $ \mathsf{ZF} $, he proved that in $ L $, all axioms of $ \mathsf{ZF} $ hold as well as the axiom of constructibility, and that the axiom of choice and the generalized continuum hypothesis (“for every ordinal $ \alpha $, one has $ 2^{\aleph_{\alpha}} = \aleph_{\alpha + 1} $”) follow in $ \mathsf{ZF} $ from the axiom of constructibility. | |
− | + | The class $ L $ can also be characterized as the smallest class that is a model of $ \mathsf{ZF} $ and contains all the ordinals; there are other ways of defining $ L $ (see [[#References|[2]]]–[[#References|[4]]]). The relation $ z \in L_{\alpha} $ can be expressed by a formula in the language of $ \mathsf{ZF} $, which is moreover of a simple syntactic structure (a so-called $ \Delta_{1}^{\mathsf{ZF}} $, cf. ). | |
− | + | Some results relating to constructible sets. The set of constructible real numbers (cf. [[Constructive real number|Constructive Real Number]]), that is, the set $ \mathbb{R} \cap L $ (where $ \mathbb{R} $ is the set of all real numbers, viewed as sequences of $ 0 $’s and $ 1 $’s), is a $ \Sigma_{1}^{2} $-set (see [[#References|[5]]]). It has been shown that the axiom of constructibility implies the existence of a non-Lebesgue-measurable set of real numbers of type $ \Sigma_{1}^{2} $ (see [[#References|[6]]]), the negation of the [[Suslin hypothesis|Suslin Hypothesis]] and the non-existence of measurable cardinals (see [[#References|[2]]]). | |
− | |||
− | |||
− | |||
− | |||
− | |||
− | |||
− | |||
− | |||
− | |||
− | |||
− | |||
− | Some results relating to constructible sets. The set of constructible real numbers (cf. [[Constructive real number|Constructive | ||
====References==== | ====References==== | ||
− | <table><TR><TD valign="top">[1a]</TD> <TD valign="top"> | + | <table> |
− | + | <TR><TD valign="top">[1a]</TD><TD valign="top"> K. Gödel, “The consistency of the axiom of choice and of the generalized continuum hypothesis”, ''Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA'', '''24''' (1938), pp. 556–557. </TD></TR> | |
− | + | <TR><TD valign="top">[1b]</TD><TD valign="top"> K. Gödel, “Consistency proof for the generalized continuum hypothesis”, ''Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA'', '''25''' (1939), pp. 220–224. </TD></TR> | |
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[2]</TD><TD valign="top"> T.J. Jech, “Lectures in set theory: with particular emphasis on the method of forcing”, ''Lect. Notes in Math.'', '''217''', Springer (1971). </TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[3]</TD><TD valign="top"> A. Mostowski, “Constructible sets with applications”, North-Holland (1969). </TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[4]</TD><TD valign="top"> C. Karp, “A proof of the relative consistency of the continuum hypothesis”, J. Crossley (ed.), ''Sets, models and recursion theory'', North-Holland (1967), pp. 1–32. </TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[5]</TD><TD valign="top"> J.W. Addison, “Some consequences of the axiom of constructibility”, ''Fund. Math.'', '''46''' (1959), pp. 337–357. </TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[6]</TD><TD valign="top"> P.S. Novikov, “On the non-contradictability of certain propositions of descriptive set theory”, ''Trudy Mat. Inst. Steklov.'', '''38''' (1951), pp. 279–316 (in Russian). </TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[7]</TD><TD valign="top"> U. Felgner, “Models of $ \mathsf{ZF} $-set theory”, Springer (1971). </TD></TR> | ||
+ | </table> | ||
====Comments==== | ====Comments==== | ||
− | Concerning (the notation) | + | Concerning (the notation) $ \Sigma_{1}^{2} $, see [[Descriptive set theory|Descriptive Set Theory]]. |
− | As a consequence of | + | As a consequence of Gödel’s findings, if the axioms of $ \mathsf{ZF} $ are non-contradictory, then they remain so after adding the axiom of choice and the generalized continuum hypothesis. This was the first relative consistency result of any importance for $ \mathsf{ZF} $, to be surpassed only after a quarter of a century in 1963 by Paul Cohen’s [[Forcing method|method of forcing]]. By forcing, it is known that $ \mathsf{ZF} $ cannot prove the axiom of constructibility (unless it is contradictory). Most set theorists think that there are no sufficient reasons to believe it to be true. Nevertheless, $ L $ is an important subclass of the set-theoretic universe that is well worth investigating. |
− | New results can be found in [[#References|[a1]]], which is also a good introduction to constructibility. Reference [[#References|[a2]]] contains (most of) the material touched upon in the main article. | + | New results can be found in [[#References|[a1]]], which is also a good introduction to the concept of constructibility. Reference [[#References|[a2]]] contains (most of) the material touched upon in the main article. |
====References==== | ====References==== | ||
− | <table><TR><TD valign="top">[a1]</TD> <TD valign="top"> | + | <table> |
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[a1]</TD> <TD valign="top"> K.J. Devlin, “Constructibility”, Springer (1984). </TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[a2]</TD> <TD valign="top"> T.J. Jech, “Set theory”, Acad. Press (1978), pp. 523ff (translated from German). </TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[a3]</TD> <TD valign="top"> K. Kunen, “Set theory, an introduction to independence proofs”, North-Holland (1980). </TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[a4]</TD> <TD valign="top"> K. Gödel, “The consistency of the axiom of choice and of the generalized continuum hypothesis with the axioms of set theory”, Princeton Univ. Press (1940). </TD></TR> | ||
+ | <TR><TD valign="top">[a5]</TD> <TD valign="top"> K. Devlin, “Constructibility”, J. Barwise (ed.), ''Handbook of mathematical logic'', North-Holland (1977), pp. 453–490. </TD></TR> | ||
+ | </table> |
Latest revision as of 16:12, 13 January 2021
Gödel constructible set, constructible set
A set that arises in the process of constructing sets described below. Let $ X $ be a set and $ R \subseteq X \times X $ a relation on $ X $. Then consider the first-order language $ L(R,X) $ containing (i) a binary predicate symbol $ \underline{R} $ denoting the relation $ R $ and (ii) individual constant symbols denoting the elements of $ X $ (for each $ x \in X $, its corresponding constant symbol is $ \underline{x} $). The statement “the formula $ \phi $ of the language $ L(R,X) $ is valid in the model $ M = (X,R) $” is written as $$ M \models \phi. $$
A set $ Y \subseteq X $ is called “definable” in the model $ M = (X,R) $ (or $ M $-definable) if and only if there exists a formula $ \phi(v) $ of $ L(R,X) $ with one free variable $ v $ such that $$ \forall x \in X: \quad x \in Y \iff M \models \phi(x). $$
Let $ \operatorname{Def}(M) $ denote the set of all $ M $-definable sets. To each ordinal $ \alpha $ is associated the set $ L_{\alpha} $ that is recursively defined by the relation $$ L_{\alpha} = \bigcup_{\beta < \alpha} \operatorname{Def} \left( L_{\beta},\in \!\! |_{L_{\beta}} \right), $$ where $ \in \!\! |_{L_{\beta}} $ denotes the membership relation restricted to $ L_{\beta} $. Hence, it follows that \begin{align} L_{0} & = \varnothing, \\ L_{1} & = \{ \varnothing \}, \\ L_{2} & = \{ \varnothing,\{ \varnothing \} \}, \\ & \vdots \\ L_{\omega} & = \bigcup_{n < \omega} L_{n}, \\ & \vdots \end{align}
A set $ z $ is called “constructible” if and only if there exists an ordinal $ \alpha $ such that $ z \in L_{\alpha} $. The class of all constructible sets is the (Gödel) constructible universe, denoted by $ L $. In 1938, Kurt Gödel defined $ L $ and introduced the following axiom of constructibility: Every set is constructible. On the basis of the axioms of $ \mathsf{ZF} $, he proved that in $ L $, all axioms of $ \mathsf{ZF} $ hold as well as the axiom of constructibility, and that the axiom of choice and the generalized continuum hypothesis (“for every ordinal $ \alpha $, one has $ 2^{\aleph_{\alpha}} = \aleph_{\alpha + 1} $”) follow in $ \mathsf{ZF} $ from the axiom of constructibility.
The class $ L $ can also be characterized as the smallest class that is a model of $ \mathsf{ZF} $ and contains all the ordinals; there are other ways of defining $ L $ (see [2]–[4]). The relation $ z \in L_{\alpha} $ can be expressed by a formula in the language of $ \mathsf{ZF} $, which is moreover of a simple syntactic structure (a so-called $ \Delta_{1}^{\mathsf{ZF}} $, cf. ).
Some results relating to constructible sets. The set of constructible real numbers (cf. Constructive Real Number), that is, the set $ \mathbb{R} \cap L $ (where $ \mathbb{R} $ is the set of all real numbers, viewed as sequences of $ 0 $’s and $ 1 $’s), is a $ \Sigma_{1}^{2} $-set (see [5]). It has been shown that the axiom of constructibility implies the existence of a non-Lebesgue-measurable set of real numbers of type $ \Sigma_{1}^{2} $ (see [6]), the negation of the Suslin Hypothesis and the non-existence of measurable cardinals (see [2]).
References
[1a] | K. Gödel, “The consistency of the axiom of choice and of the generalized continuum hypothesis”, Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA, 24 (1938), pp. 556–557. |
[1b] | K. Gödel, “Consistency proof for the generalized continuum hypothesis”, Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA, 25 (1939), pp. 220–224. |
[2] | T.J. Jech, “Lectures in set theory: with particular emphasis on the method of forcing”, Lect. Notes in Math., 217, Springer (1971). |
[3] | A. Mostowski, “Constructible sets with applications”, North-Holland (1969). |
[4] | C. Karp, “A proof of the relative consistency of the continuum hypothesis”, J. Crossley (ed.), Sets, models and recursion theory, North-Holland (1967), pp. 1–32. |
[5] | J.W. Addison, “Some consequences of the axiom of constructibility”, Fund. Math., 46 (1959), pp. 337–357. |
[6] | P.S. Novikov, “On the non-contradictability of certain propositions of descriptive set theory”, Trudy Mat. Inst. Steklov., 38 (1951), pp. 279–316 (in Russian). |
[7] | U. Felgner, “Models of $ \mathsf{ZF} $-set theory”, Springer (1971). |
Comments
Concerning (the notation) $ \Sigma_{1}^{2} $, see Descriptive Set Theory.
As a consequence of Gödel’s findings, if the axioms of $ \mathsf{ZF} $ are non-contradictory, then they remain so after adding the axiom of choice and the generalized continuum hypothesis. This was the first relative consistency result of any importance for $ \mathsf{ZF} $, to be surpassed only after a quarter of a century in 1963 by Paul Cohen’s method of forcing. By forcing, it is known that $ \mathsf{ZF} $ cannot prove the axiom of constructibility (unless it is contradictory). Most set theorists think that there are no sufficient reasons to believe it to be true. Nevertheless, $ L $ is an important subclass of the set-theoretic universe that is well worth investigating.
New results can be found in [a1], which is also a good introduction to the concept of constructibility. Reference [a2] contains (most of) the material touched upon in the main article.
References
[a1] | K.J. Devlin, “Constructibility”, Springer (1984). |
[a2] | T.J. Jech, “Set theory”, Acad. Press (1978), pp. 523ff (translated from German). |
[a3] | K. Kunen, “Set theory, an introduction to independence proofs”, North-Holland (1980). |
[a4] | K. Gödel, “The consistency of the axiom of choice and of the generalized continuum hypothesis with the axioms of set theory”, Princeton Univ. Press (1940). |
[a5] | K. Devlin, “Constructibility”, J. Barwise (ed.), Handbook of mathematical logic, North-Holland (1977), pp. 453–490. |
Gödel constructive set. Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=G%C3%B6del_constructive_set&oldid=22513