Namespaces
Variants
Actions

Difference between revisions of "User:Whayes43"

From Encyclopedia of Mathematics
Jump to: navigation, search
(Created page with " The quadratic formula is $-b \pm \sqrt{b^2 - 4ac} \over 2a$ $$ \sum f(x) = F(x) + g(x) $$")
 
Line 1: Line 1:
 
  
 
The quadratic formula is $-b \pm \sqrt{b^2 - 4ac} \over 2a$
 
The quadratic formula is $-b \pm \sqrt{b^2 - 4ac} \over 2a$
Line 6: Line 5:
 
   \sum f(x) = F(x) + g(x)
 
   \sum f(x) = F(x) + g(x)
 
$$
 
$$
 +
 +
-----
 +
 +
In his paper of 1817, Bolzano undertakes to prove the following theorem about the roots of a polynomial equation in one real variable:<ref>Russ p. 181</ref>
 +
:If a function of the form
 +
::$xn + axn-I + bxn-2 + *** + px + q$
 +
:in which $n$ denotes a whole positive number, is positive for $x = \alpha$ and negative for $x = \beta$, then the equation
 +
::$xn + axn-1 + bxn-2 +***+ px + q = 0$
 +
:has at least one real root lying between $\alpha$ and $\beta$.
 +
 +
In his preferatory remarks, Bolzano examines in detail all previous proofs of the intermediate value theorem, many of which, including Gauss' first proof of 1799, depend "on a truth borrowed from geometry." Bolzano rejects all such proofs in totality and unequivocally:<ref>Russ p. 160</ref>
 +
:It is an intolerable offense against correct method to derive truths of pure (or general) mathematics (i.e., arithmetic, algebra, analysis) from considerations which belong to a merely applied (or special) part, namely, geometry....  A strictly scientific proof, or the objective reason, of a truth which holds equally for all quantities, whether in space or not, cannot possibly lie in a truth which holds merely for quantities which are in space.
 +
 +
In the process of proving the main theorem stated above, Bolzano achieves the following intermediate results:<ref>Russ p. 157</ref>
 +
 +
(a) the formal definition of the continuity of a function of one real variable, stated as follows:
 +
:a function $f(x)$ varies according to the law of continuity for all values of $x$ inside or outside certain limits means that if $x$ is some such value, the difference $f(x + \omega) - f(x)$ can be made smaller than any given quantity provided $\omega$ can be taken as small as we please. With the notation I introduced in Section 14 of ''Binomische Lehrsatz'', etc. (Prague, 1816), this is $f(x + \omega) = f(x) + \Omega$
 +
 +
(b) the criterion for the (pointwise) convergence of an infinite series, although the proof of its sufficiency, prior to any definition or construction of the real numbers, is inevitably inadequate:
 +
: If a series of quantities
 +
Fix, F2x, F3x, . . . . Fnx, . . . . Fn+rx,...
 +
has the property that the difference between its.nth term FnX and every later term F,+,x, however far from the former, remains smaller than any given quantity if n has been taken large enough, then there is always a certain constant quantity, and indeed only one, which the terms of this series approach, and to which they can come as close as desired if the series is continued far enough.
 +
 +
(c) the original form of the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem, stated as follows:
 +
: If a property $M$ does not belong to all values of a variable $x$, but does belong to all values which are less than a certain $u$, then there is always a quantity $U$ which is the greatest of those of which it can be asserted that all smaller $x$ have property $M$
 +
 +
(d) the intermediate value theorem, stated in a form that is now sometimes called Bolzano's theorem, which Bolzano himself believed to be "a more general truth" than the main theorem to be proved:
 +
: if two functions of $x$, $f(x)$ and $g(x)$, vary according to the law of continuity either for all values $x$ or only for those which lie between $\alpha$ and $\beta$, and if $f(\alpha) < g(\alpha)$ and $f(\beta) > g(\beta)$, then there is always a certain value of $x$ between $\alpha$ and $\beta$ for which $f(x) = g(x)$
 +
 +
==Notes==
 +
<references/>
 +
==Primary sources==
 +
* Bolzano, Bernard (1817). ''Rein analytischer Beweis des Lehrsatzes, dass zwischen je zwey Werthen, die ein entgegengesetzes Resultat gewahren, wenigstens eine reelle Wurzel der Gleichung liege''. ["Purely analytic proof of the theorem that between any two values which give results of opposite sign there lies at least one real root of the equation"]. Prague.
 +
==References==
 +
* Russ, S. B. "A Translation of Bolzano's Paper on the Intermediate Value Theorem," ''Historia Mathematica'' 7 (1980), 156-185.

Revision as of 00:49, 20 May 2014

The quadratic formula is $-b \pm \sqrt{b^2 - 4ac} \over 2a$

$$ \sum f(x) = F(x) + g(x) $$


In his paper of 1817, Bolzano undertakes to prove the following theorem about the roots of a polynomial equation in one real variable:[1]

If a function of the form
$xn + axn-I + bxn-2 + *** + px + q$ :in which $n$ denotes a whole positive number, is positive for $x = \alpha$ and negative for $x = \beta$, then the equation ::$xn + axn-1 + bxn-2 +***+ px + q = 0$ :has at least one real root lying between $\alpha$ and $\beta$. In his preferatory remarks, Bolzano examines in detail all previous proofs of the intermediate value theorem, many of which, including Gauss' first proof of 1799, depend "on a truth borrowed from geometry." Bolzano rejects all such proofs in totality and unequivocally:'"`UNIQ--ref-00000001-QINU`"' :It is an intolerable offense against correct method to derive truths of pure (or general) mathematics (i.e., arithmetic, algebra, analysis) from considerations which belong to a merely applied (or special) part, namely, geometry.... A strictly scientific proof, or the objective reason, of a truth which holds equally for all quantities, whether in space or not, cannot possibly lie in a truth which holds merely for quantities which are in space. In the process of proving the main theorem stated above, Bolzano achieves the following intermediate results:'"`UNIQ--ref-00000002-QINU`"' (a) the formal definition of the continuity of a function of one real variable, stated as follows: :a function $f(x)$ varies according to the law of continuity for all values of $x$ inside or outside certain limits means that if $x$ is some such value, the difference $f(x + \omega) - f(x)$ can be made smaller than any given quantity provided $\omega$ can be taken as small as we please. With the notation I introduced in Section 14 of ''Binomische Lehrsatz'', etc. (Prague, 1816), this is $f(x + \omega) = f(x) + \Omega$ (b) the criterion for the (pointwise) convergence of an infinite series, although the proof of its sufficiency, prior to any definition or construction of the real numbers, is inevitably inadequate: : If a series of quantities Fix, F2x, F3x, . . . . Fnx, . . . . Fn+rx,... has the property that the difference between its.nth term FnX and every later term F,+,x, however far from the former, remains smaller than any given quantity if n has been taken large enough, then there is always a certain constant quantity, and indeed only one, which the terms of this series approach, and to which they can come as close as desired if the series is continued far enough. (c) the original form of the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem, stated as follows: : If a property $M$ does not belong to all values of a variable $x$, but does belong to all values which are less than a certain $u$, then there is always a quantity $U$ which is the greatest of those of which it can be asserted that all smaller $x$ have property $M$ (d) the intermediate value theorem, stated in a form that is now sometimes called Bolzano's theorem, which Bolzano himself believed to be "a more general truth" than the main theorem to be proved: : if two functions of $x$, $f(x)$ and $g(x)$, vary according to the law of continuity either for all values $x$ or only for those which lie between $\alpha$ and $\beta$, and if $f(\alpha) < g(\alpha)$ and $f(\beta) > g(\beta)$, then there is always a certain value of $x$ between $\alpha$ and $\beta$ for which $f(x) = g(x)$

Notes

  1. Russ p. 181
  2. Russ p. 160
  3. Russ p. 157

Primary sources

  • Bolzano, Bernard (1817). Rein analytischer Beweis des Lehrsatzes, dass zwischen je zwey Werthen, die ein entgegengesetzes Resultat gewahren, wenigstens eine reelle Wurzel der Gleichung liege. ["Purely analytic proof of the theorem that between any two values which give results of opposite sign there lies at least one real root of the equation"]. Prague.

References

  • Russ, S. B. "A Translation of Bolzano's Paper on the Intermediate Value Theorem," Historia Mathematica 7 (1980), 156-185.
How to Cite This Entry:
Whayes43. Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=Whayes43&oldid=32190