Namespaces
Variants
Actions

Suslin hypothesis

From Encyclopedia of Mathematics
Revision as of 17:25, 7 February 2011 by 127.0.0.1 (talk) (Importing text file)
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)
Jump to: navigation, search
The printable version is no longer supported and may have rendering errors. Please update your browser bookmarks and please use the default browser print function instead.

A hypothesis that states that every linearly ordered set without first and last elements that is moreover complete, dense and satisfies the Suslin condition, is isomorphic to the real line. Here, completeness signifies the existence of a least upper bound for every non-empty bounded subset, density denotes the non-emptiness of any interval , , and the Suslin condition requires that every family of pairwise-disjoint intervals is countable. The real line possesses all the properties that figure in the formulation of the Suslin hypothesis. The Suslin hypothesis thus states that the above properties of an ordered set define it completely. This hypothesis was formulated in 1920 by M.Ya. Suslin [1].

Within the framework of the system ZFC (the system ZF with the axiom of choice) it is impossible to prove or disprove the Suslin hypothesis, assuming that ZF is consistent. It follows from Gödel's axiom of constructibility (see Gödel constructive set) that the negation of the Suslin hypothesis holds. The consistency of the Suslin hypothesis with the axioms of ZFC is proved by the construction of a corresponding model, using a variant of the forcing method (iterated forcing). The addition of the continuum hypothesis to ZFC does not give either a positive or negative solution of the Suslin hypothesis.

The Suslin hypothesis and its generalizations have had a great influence on the development of axiomatic set theory. Many ideas and methods have been worked out in conjunction with it. These include Jensen's combinatorial principles and (see [4]), the theory of the fine structure of the constructible hierarchy (see [5]), Martin's axiom [7], and the iterated forcing method [2].

Jensen's principle : A subset of a cardinal number is said to be closed unbounded if it contains all its limit points and if, for any , there is a such that . A set is said to be stationary if its intersection with every closed unbounded subset of a cardinal number is non-empty.

Jensen's principle : There exists a sequence , , such that for every the set is stationary. For every regular , the principle follows from the axiom of constructibility, while the negation of the Suslin hypothesis follows from . Jensen's combinatorial principles, as well as Martin's axiom (see below), have been successfully used in topology (see [4], [6], [8]).

Let be a partially ordered set. A set is called dense if for every there is a such that . A set is said to be compatible if for any finite subset there is a such that for every . Two elements and from are said to be incompatible if the set is not compatible. It is said that a partially ordered set satisfies the countable anti-chain condition if every set that consists of pairwise-incompatible elements is countable. Martin's axiom (MA) states the following: If a partially ordered set satisfies the countable anti-chain condition and if is a family of dense subsets of cardinality less than , then there is a compatible set such that for every the intersection is non-empty.

In the presence of the continuum hypothesis (CH), Martin's axiom can be proved. The most interesting results are obtained by a combination of Martin's axiom (MA) and the negation of the continuum hypothesis . The principle contradicts the combination , since implies CH. It often turns out that a result that can be inferred from will be disproved under the assumption . This is, e.g., the case with the Suslin hypothesis. Indeed, implies the Suslin hypothesis, while implies the negation of the Suslin hypothesis.

The combination is compatible with ZFC if ZF is consistent.

References

[1] M. [M.Ya. Suslin] Souslin, "Problème 3" Fundam. Math. , 1 (1920) pp. 223
[2] K.J. Devlin, H. Johnsbråten, "The Souslin problem" , Lect. notes in math. , 405 , Springer (1974)
[3] T.J. Jech, "Lectures in set theory: with particular emphasis on the method of forcing" , Lect. notes in math. , 217 , Springer (1971)
[4] J. Barwise (ed.) , Handbook of mathematical logic , North-Holland (1977) pp. Chapts. B4-B7
[5] K.J. Devlin, "Aspects of constructibility" , Lect. notes in math. , 354 , Springer (1973)
[6] V.V. Fedorchuk, "Completely closed mappings and the compatibility of certain general topology theorems with the axioms of set theory" Mat. Sb. , 99 : 1 (1976) pp. 3–33 (In Russian)
[7] D.A. Martin, R. Solovay, "Internal Cohen extensions" Ann. Math. Logic , 2 (1970) pp. 143–178
[8] V.I. Malykhin, "Topology and forcing" Russian Math. Surveys , 38 : 1 (1983) pp. 77–136 Uspekhi Mat. Nauk , 38 : 1 (1983) pp. 69–118


Comments

Jensen's combinatorial principles and are called diamond and square, respectively. The countable anti-chain condition is sometimes called the countable chain condition, and is then also abbreviated to ccc.

References

[a1] K.J. Devlin, "Constructibility" , Springer (1984)
[a2] D.H. Fremlin, "Consequences of Martin's axiom" , Cambridge Univ. Press (1984)
[a3] T.J. Jech, "Multiple forcing" , Cambridge Univ. Press (1986)
[a4] T.J. Jech, "Set theory" , Acad. Press (1978) (Translated from German)
[a5] K. Kunen, "Set theory, an introduction to independence proofs" , North-Holland (1980)
How to Cite This Entry:
Suslin hypothesis. Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=Suslin_hypothesis&oldid=18257
This article was adapted from an original article by V.N. Grishin (originator), which appeared in Encyclopedia of Mathematics - ISBN 1402006098. See original article